
© Council for the
Development of Social Science Research in Africa, 2012
(ISSN 0850-3907)
Revealed
Preference Theory, Rationality, and
Neoclassical
Economics: Science or Ideology
Lansana Keita*
Abstract
Revealed
Preference Theory (Samuelson 1938) is an attempt to establish economic theory
as a genuine empirical science by ridding it of nonempirical psychological
concepts. Samuelson’s goal was to rid economic theory of the last vestiges of
utility analysis. Samuelson structured his theory on a set of preference axioms
that would explain the choices of economic agents. But revealed preference
theory is rendered problematic because decision making is structured therein on
preferences that conform to an implicit postulate of rationality. Matters are
further compounded by the fact that despite theoretical support offered by
theorists such as Varian, the empirical results demonstrate that agent decision
making is often at variance with the formal axioms of revealed preference. The
issue is not solved even when decision making is construed within the context
of imperfect, that is, ‘bounded rationality’.
I argue that
neoclassical economic theory is best understood as a form of rule
utilitarianism. In this regard, neoclassical economics is unavoidably
value-laden and should be construed as an aspect of normative welfare
economics. Thus efforts by theorists such as Vanberg to salvage the assumed
scientific credentials of neoclassical economics by construing the postulate of
rationality in evolutionary terms are seen as problematic. Neoclassical
economic theory is to be viewed essentially then as an ideology that presents a
particular theory of human behaviour. It is this theory that serves as the
foundations of modern capitalism and its practise as neoliberal economics. This
is the anthropological question then: is such an ideology socially optimal for
humans as social animals in terms of efficiency and equity?

* Department of Economics
and Political Science,
Kwara State University,
Nigeria. Email:
keitalans@yahoo.com
74
Résumé
La
Théorie de la préférence révélée(Samuelson 1938) est une tentative d’établir
une théorie économique comme étant une authentique science empirique en la
débarrassant de tout concept psychologique nonempirique. Par ce moyen,
Samuelson cherchait à débarrasser la théorie économique des derniers vestiges
de l’analyse de la fonction d’utilité. 0Samuelson a structuré sa théorie autour
d’un ensemble d’axiomes de préférence qui permettrait d’expliquer les choix des
opérateurs économiques. Mais la théorie de la préférence révélée est rendue
problématique, car la prise de décision y est structurée sur la base des
préférences conformes à un postulat implicite de rationalité. Cela devient
encore plus compliqué si on y ajoute le fait que malgré le soutien théorique
apporté par ses tenants tels que Varian, les résultats empiriques démontrent
que la prise de décision par l’opérateur varie souvent par rapport aux axiomes
formels de la préférence révélée. Ce
problème n’est
pas résolu
même quand la prise de décision est interprétée dans le contexte de la
rationalité imparfaite, pour ne pas dire « circonscrite ». J’affirme que la
théorie économique néo-classique est mieux comprise comme une forme de règle de
l’utilitarisme. A cet égard, l’économie néo-classique est inévitablement
chargée de valeur et devrait être interprétée comme un aspect de l’économie
normative de bien-être. Ainsi, les efforts de théoriciens tels que Vanberg pour
sauver la prétendue identité scientifique de l’économie néo-classique, en
interprétant le postulat de rationalité en termes évolutionnistes sont
ressentis comme étant problématiques. La théorie économique néo-classique doit
être dès lors perçue essentiellement comme une idéologie qui présente une
théorie donnée du comportement humain. C’est sur cette théorie que se fonde le
capitalisme moderne et sa pratique en tant qu’économie néolibérale. La question
anthropologique est donc celle-ci : Une telle idéologie, est-elle socialement
optimale pour les humains considérés comme animaux sociaux, en termes
d’efficacité et d’équité ?
Preamble
John Maynard Keynes,
arguably the most influential economist of the 20th century, and originator –
along with Harry Dexter White of the US Treasury – of the well-known Bretton
Woods institutions, the IMF and the International
Bank for Reconstruction and Development
(IBRD), now the World Bank, wrote the following in his 1936 General Theory of Employment, Interest, and
Money:
The ideas of economists and
political philosophers, both when they are right and when they are wrong, are
more powerful than is commonly understood. Indeed the world is ruled by little
else. Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any
intellectual influence, are usually the 75
slaves of
some defunct economist. Madmen in authority, who hear voices in the air, are
distilling their frenzy from some academic scribbler of a few years back. I am
sure that the power of vested interests is vastly exaggerated compared with the
gradual encroachment of ideas (Keynes 1936:383).
I cite the above because most human
beings live their economic lives without reflecting on the precepts, concepts,
and rules that they take for granted : the use of money, prices, inflation,
interest rates, capital, etc. Yet, it is the influence of ideas about how
humans in society produce and consume that determines their life chances,
especially in Africa and the rest of the socalled Third World.
The economic system under which contemporary Africa lives
is not one of traditional village reciprocity and redistribution; it is one
determined by the dominant capitalist market system and its rules long
established by economists and politicians in the West. It is a world of private
property where those who own private capital are supposed to be free to invest
that capital as they see fit, in free and open markets. In this context, the
role of government is mainly to supervise market operations so as to ensure
macroeconomic discipline. Whether in their activities some individuals become
poor and destitute and others acquire great wealth is not really a matter for
pure market economic theory. The goal is maximal market efficiency where
rational decisions concerning the allocation of limited resources are supposed
to be made. The theoretical basis for this is what is known as neoclassical
economics, a positive empirical science according to its theorists. The applied
side of neoclassical economics is what is known as ‘neoliberal economics’, the
catechism of the cohorts of acolytes who administer its rituals and rites at
global institutions such as the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the World
Bank.
And this neoclassical
economics system – as a rule-governed neoliberal economics – dominates the
economic activity of the world through the above-
mentioned institutions and the World
Trade Organisation (WTO). Neoclassical
economics and its neoliberal rules represent the system of global capitalism. But this system just does
not stand by itself, it is promoted and advanced throughout the world. This is the system of economics that is
taught in most universities in the world including Africa. But the point here
is that students are taught to accept the neoclassical description of economic
reality as if it were scientifically valid in intent at least. The language is
heavily quantitative, thereby giving the impression of science in action. Just
as with religious dogma, there is no room for alternatives. But in reality the
function of neoclassical economics is to reify and justify the ideological
theory of market capitalism.
76
This should be an interesting observation regarding Africa,
given that capitalism has not treated Africa well. Low wages, high
unemployment, centreperiphery unequal exchanges, high prices, exploited and
abused open markets that drive local producers into poverty, incessant dreams
of fleeing to the West to do the work the Euro-Americans are not too keen about
doing, poor and often costly education, equally poor housing and health care.
So it behoves the African student of economics to ponder the results of a
meta-analysis of neoclassical economics as it strove to establish itself as a
science in order to cement the claim that capitalist market economics describes
the natural and optimal behaviour and decision making of humans.
Introduction
In 1938 Paul
Samuelson published a paper titled ‘ A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s
Behaviour’ (Economica, February
1938:61-73) in which he sought to settle once and for all the issue of how to
establish the research discipline of economics on firm scientific moorings.
Samuelson’s paper is important because for 100 years prior to his paper there
were serious methodological debates by theorists of economics on the need for
economics to establish itself as a science on epistemological par with the
natural sciences such as chemistry and physics.
It was in the 1840s that William
Whewell argued that empirical science, then known as ‘natural philosophy’,
should thenceforth be known as natural science – mainly because research in
physics and chemistry was firmly and restrictedly confined to the empirical
world – with no room left for the results of non-empirical or metaphysical
speculation. It was on this basis that John Stuart Mill published his Logic of the Moral Sciences in which he
argued that Economics was a deductive
science rather an inductive one.
Subsequent to Mill and other
theorists of economics such as Cairnes, the debate centred on how to wean
economics as an objective science away from political economy which was wont to
nurture issues of values and ethics. This was the context in which theorists
such as Alfred Marshall and John Neville Keynes debated the future of economics
as a research discipline.
John Neville Keynes, for example,
argued that the foundations of economics should be those of a positive science
which would serve as the basis for its prescriptive or normative side. The same
approach held for Marshall and Sidgwick who argued along the same lines, that
economics should be a positive science as distinct from its normative or
prescriptive considerations. But there was much opposition from those who
wanted to maintain the idea of economics, then known as political economy, as
an
77
essentially moral science, that is one for
which the ethical considerations relevant to human welfare were paramount.
One may wonder, parenthetically, why the antecedents of
modern neoclassical economics all seem to be of Anglo-Saxon origin,
specifically British, and almost all having their intellectual bases at Oxford,
Cambridge and later the London School of Economics. The reason is that Britain
was the first modern nation to industrialise and to become the world’s leader
in trade and commerce. But this pre-eminence also stemmed from the fact that
the dominant British intellectual classes had adopted empiricism rather than
abstract rationalism as the most effective way of understanding and controlling
phenomena in the world. In this regard, the empiricist view of phenomena
developed by Locke, Berkley and Hume was central and seminal.
The empiricist view of things also served as the
methodological foundations not only for the natural sciences but also for the
social sciences, especially economics. But the social sciences dealt with the
behavioural life of humans whose phenomenal states of being are radically
different from the phenomena studied by the natural sciences. The point is that
whereas the behaviours of the objects of the natural sciences were to be
studied purely in terms of their physical or empirical manifestations, the
objects of the social sciences required study not only of external or empirical
manifestation of human behaviours but also the non-empirical causes of such
behaviours.
Such behaviours were properly understood not only in
terms of their physical causes but also in terms of their non-empirically
accessible reasons. There was also a valuation component to human decision
making and behaviour because most of human behaviour was non-instinctual – hence
derived from conscious deliberation. And the conscious acts of such
deliberation were necessarily evaluated along ethical lines. This was the
dilemma faced by those theorists who wanted to establish economics on firm
scientific grounds. The only solution that was possible at the time was to
appeal to the seemingly empiricist theory of human decision making afforded by
utilitarianism. The fundamental assumption of utilitarianism as an ethical
system was that the ethical concepts of good and bad, desirable or undesirable
were ultimately reducible to the concepts of pleasure and pain. And such were
measurable according to the felicific calculus of Bentham, one of the founders
of the ethical school of thought known as utilitarianism.
It was on this basis that the concept of utility was
adopted by the budding science of positive economics. This approach also
coincided with the individualist approach to economics as evidenced by the
marginalist paradigm developed by Jevons (Theory
of Political Economy,London, Macmillan,1879), Walras (Elements of Pure Economics, Lausanne, Corbaz,1874) and Menger
78
(Principles of Economics, New York,1871,
and New York University Press, 1976[English translation]). It was against this
background that the concepts of utils, cardinal (measurable) utility,
maximisation of satisfaction, and so on, developed. The issue at stake was how
to establish a scientific theory that explained the economic behaviour of human
agents.
But this ambitious enterprise
experienced failure because it was soon realized that utility could not be
measured since it was a purely introspective appraisal determined by the agent
himself or herself. Furthermore, there could be no publicly observable
measuring instrument to determine such, given that interpersonal comparisons of
utility were not possible in any determinable scientific sense. The solution
was to drop the cardinal requirement and rely only on the consumer’s ordinal
ranking of preferences.
This was the
inception of standard utility analysis according to ordinal rankings. But
again, this approach was based on the subjective utility rankings of the agent
himself or herself.
The point is that this approach
could not be tolerated for long by those theorists who were arguing that
neoclassical economics, in its positive mode, should be a genuine science
through and through. This is where Paul Samuelson’s theory of revealed
preference comes into play. Samuelson’s theory of revealed preference as
expressed in his paper (Samuelson 1938[a]):61-73) was presented as a solution
to the problem or ridding scientific economics of those lingering mentalist
assumptions embedded initially in cardinal utility theory then later in the
ordinal utility configuration. It is for this reason that Samuelson wrote that
the aim of his paper was as follows: ‘ I propose, therefore, that we start anew
in direct attack upon the problem, dropping off the last vestiges of the
utility analysis. This does not preclude the introduction of utility by any who
may care to do so, nor will it contradict the results attained by use of
related constructs. It is merely that the analysis can be carried on more
directly, and from a different set of postulates’. (Samuelson 1938[a] in
Stiglitz [ed.] 1996:4).
Samuelson’s goal was to
offer a purely scientific theory of agent behaviour as an improvement over the
Hicks-Allen programme founded on the ordinal theory of utility. And as he put
it in the concluding paragraph of his paper: ‘I have tried here to develop the
theory of consumer’s behaviour freed from any vestigial traces of the utility
concept’ (Samuelson 1966:13). The reason why Samuelson was concerned to do this
is that he subscribed to the view that economics – in this sense, neoclassical
economics – should be an avowedly empirical science whose methodology should
subscribe to the research paradigm of operationalism.
79 What
I propose to do in this paper is to critically evaluate Samuelson’s attempt to
rid economics of its ordinal utility foundations which he later developed in
his 1948 paper, ‘Consumption Theory in terms of Revealed Preference’ (Samuelson
1966:64-74) as the ‘revealed preference theory’. I will argue that the
theoretical foundations of Samuelson’s revealed preference theory are
problematic and, as a result, Samuelson’s goal of establishing a genuine
science of economics is compromised. The issue is whether any agent choice
(revealed preference) can be shown to be truly reflective of that agent’s
preferences. The issue also involves the question of whether Samuelson’s
revealed preference theory should just have focused on explaining agent choice
without reference to preference – a subjective non-empirical concept. But then
the goal of empirical science is to explain and predict phenomena in the
empirical world. The question then is: has the revealed preference theory
succeeded in this?
The more important question though is whether a genuine
empirical science of economics is possible? If not, the claim that modern
neoclassical economics is rightfully demarcated into a scientific side and a
normative (prescriptive) side would be seriously cast in doubt. It would be
obvious then that economics should properly redefine itself as traditional
political economy did, according to which, issues of fact and value, efficiency
and equity, social empathy, etc, were epistemologically bound together. There
is the alternative solution to the issue though, given that human behaviour in
all its dimensions is empirical. Human behaviour could be examined empirically
and scientifically in much the same way that ethologists study animal behaviour
and anthropologists study the behaviour of humans in traditional non-Western
settings.
I will proceed as follows: first will be a discussion of
what constitutes a proper scientific theory and it will then be determined
whether Samuelson’s revealed preference theory conforms to it – especially in
terms of his adoption of operationalism as his theoretical paradigm. I will
then discuss Samuelson’s revealed preference theory and the responses to it by
authors such as Houthakker, Sen, Wong, Varian, Grune, et al. Finally, I will
argue that contemporary neoclassical theory as it evolved in the last several
decades has been misguided in its attempts to establish neoclassical theory as
a scientific theory. In this regard, neoclassical theory has been used as an
ideological tool to defend a world of great economic disparities between
people. This is the world of modern capitalism. I will then discuss the
attempts by theorists such as Vanberg to salvage the neoclassical model as an
adaptive system of human decision-making. But this approach would not solve the
problem concerning the status of economics as a science. The argument 80 eventually
leads to the conclusion that neoclassical economics is implicitly and
essentially an aspect of value theory – utilitarianism; more specifically preference
utilitarianism. But this outcome is certainly problematic given that human
behaviour is empirically given. This is the basis for my foray into economic
anthropology as a way of formulating a comprehensive analysis of human
behaviour.
On the Practice and Theory of Science
For working
scientists, an acceptable scientific theory is one which makes claims about
some aspect of the empirical world that is subject to scrutiny by other
scientists and repeatable under the experimental conditions described in the
research. In other words, an orthodox scientific theory makes claims about the
structure of some aspects of the world in terms of explaining the results of
its attendant experiment. The experiment always assumes the validity of the
attendant theory’s principles, postulates, laws, etc, that explain and predict
the processes in question. The point being made here is that for the working
scientist, certain assumptions are implicitly made about scientific research. A
successful scientific theory offers a picture and description of how some
aspect of the empirical world actually is or at least appears.
The fact is that a successful
theory is a confident plea for ontological certitude. When the theory predicts
certain results and they consistently occur under experimental conditions, the
assumptions, principles and laws in question are assumed to be valid and are
assumed to be explanatory of the phenomena involved. When certain experimental
results are called into question the issue is not that the goals of science are
being questioned but that the experiments were poorly constructed or that the
basic hypothetical assumptions are erroneous. Research results are called into
question when experimental conditions cannot be replicated or predicted results
are not forthcoming. A basic assumption held by research scientists is that the
empirical world actually exists and is knowable.
Working scientists take
assumptions about the empirical world for granted but that is not the case with
those who study science theoretically. In the last few decades there have been
questions raised about the growth of science. The early assumption argued for
by the logical positivists is that science progressed cumulatively as its
practitioners delved further into the structure of phenomena.
The positivist approach was the
standard approach for researchers such as Carnap and Hempel into the structure
and methodology of science. Their goal was to explicate the logic of science.
Matters changed with the novel approach offered by Thomas Kuhn in his Structure of Scientific Revolutions 81 (Kuhn1962).
Kuhn’s basic thesis is that each successful scientific theory is founded on its
own ontological and epistemological paradigm. And the way science makes
progress, according to Kuhn, is by way of the scientific revolution. Each
scientific theory is contextualised into its particular paradigm which carries
its own internal dynamics. As research on the research phenomenon continues,
anomalies and inconsistencies build up within the experimental structure. When
attempts to solve the anomalies fail, crisis sets in and an extra-contextual
new paradigm develops to offer novel explanations. It is in this way that
scientific progress continues, according to Kuhn.
The key point in Kuhn’s thesis is the claim that successful
theories could be incommensurable, that is, incompatible. Critics of Kuhn argue
that this approach renders scientific research relativistic, which is at odds
with the objectivist goals of science. Karl Popper (1972) in Objective Knowledge, for example, has
raised questions about this approach to scientific research on the part of
Kuhn. According to Popper and others, the cardinal error committed by Kuhn is his
assumption that valid scientific theories may be committed only to their
paradigms and not to an underlying empirical reality.
In this regard, prominent theorists such as Popper
(1968) argued for the method of falsification as the most appropriate means of
testing scientific theories. The essence of Popper’s falsificationist
methodology is that a genuine scientific theory should contain real ontological
content which could be shown to be confirmed or falsified within appropriate
contexts. This approach, later fleshed out as ‘critical rationalism’, has been
adopted by some theorists such as Mark Blaug (1980),who defines himself as
being committed to Popper’s falsificationist approach.
Given the continuing success of standard scientific
practice founded on the principle that scientific theories and their
constituent concepts must be anchored ontologically in the empirical world,
debates among scientists concerning falsificationism, or whether observation
terms and propositions are theory-laden or not, hardly resonate with working
scientists. The rules of thumb for modern scientific practitioners are as
follows: 1) Are claimed empirical results predictable according to background
theory, replicable? 2) The mark of the success of a scientific theory is whether
the theory successfully predicts and explains. 3) Replicable predicted outcomes
are subject to experimental control in the form of the logical rules of modus tollens and modus ponens. 4) Repeatable predictions of particular theories
signal that their constituent theoretical and observational terms do possess
empirical content. Admittedly, there are areas of modern science, such as
quantum mechanics, that researchers find problematic, but the field has never
eschewed experimental analysis given that it continues to place great stock in
predictions.
82
Economics and the Methods of Science
In the above
discussion we have examined the working methodologies of working scientists in
their field. It was obvious that contemporary scientific research is founded on
how successful theories are in terms of their predictions. It is on this basis
that theories that successfully predict are regarded as valid. And it is the
predictive power of a theory that confers legitimacy on its equally important
explanatory power. But what does a valid explanation entail? It entails
assumptions, postulates, concepts, laws, and principles that are ontologically
real. Theoreticians of economics have wrestled with this issue for some time
now The key question has always been how to deal with the troublesome issue of
prediction in human decision-making. The generally unsatisfactory results have
as a result cast ontological doubt on the assumptions of economic theory.
Despite a reputation as a pure
technician of neoclassical economic theory, Paul Samuelson actually made
important comments on the theory of science as it applies to economics. The
leading theory of science during the period of Samuelson’s intellectual
development was the operationalism of physicist
Percy Bridgman,
which he formulated in his textThe Logic
of Modern Physics (Bridgman 1927). The basic idea behind operationalism was
that the scientific tenor of a theory was determined by its operational
significance, that is, by an empirical demonstration of the theory in
operation. Thus for Bridgman, the concept of length was operationally defined
when an object was actually measured (Bridgman 1927:5).
Another aspect of
Samuelson’s operationalism was ‘descriptivism’, which states that scientific
theories merely describe phenomena as they present themselves empirically.
Consider Samuelson’s reply to Fritz Machlup’s claim that the bulk of economic
theory is based on counterfactual assumptions and ‘contains only theoretical
constructs and no operational concepts and yields results which we hope point
to elements of truth present in complex situations’ (Fritz Machlup 1966 in
Stiglitz [ed.]:760). Samuelson writes: ‘Scientists never “explain” any
behaviour by theory or by any other hook. Every description that is superseded
by a “deeper explanation” turns out on careful examination to have been
replaced by still another description, albeit possibly a more useful
description that covers and illuminates a wider area’
(Samuelson 1966:762).
Thus we see that Samuelson is
strongly committed to descriptivism as the goal of his operationalist
methodology. It should be noticed in this regard that operationalism is
synonymous with explanation. It is on this basis that Samuelson takes issue with
the methodology of economics offered by another prominent theorist of
economics, Milton Friedman. Friedman (1953:3-43)
83
argues that the validity
of a scientific theory depends essentially on its predictive tenor. In this
regard, Friedman’s methodology has rightfully been called instrumentalist. For
Friedman, the assumptions of a theory are of minor import in terms of their
empirical content. This position is obviously at odds with Samuelson’s strict
operationalist descriptivism. Samuelson refers to Friedman’s instrumentalist
methodology as the ‘F-Twist’. In reply to
Friedman, Samuelson argues that the
predictions C of some theory B constitute an integral part of the theory
itself. But B must contain its own set of assumptions, A, which must possess
the same realism content as C itself. In other words, for the descriptivist
Samuelson, the assumptions of some theory B are logically and empirically
connected to its predictions, C. Thus, the predictive results of a theory are
entailed by the realism or unrealism of its assumptions. This is the basis for
Samuelson’s attempt to ground
fundamental economic theory on foundations
that are empirically realistic.
An interesting discussion of the methodological
debate between the operationalism of Samuelson and the instrumentalism of
Friedman is provided by Stanley Wong’s critique of Samuelson’s scientific
methodology and his revealed preference theory (Wong 1973, 1978). Wong’s
methodological approach is that of a critical empiricist given his assiduous
dissection of Samuelson’s epistemological wrestling with the concepts of
utility theory and revealed preference. But Wong is committed to the idea of
economics as a science and does not venture further than mere critique. The
question is: if Samuelson’s revealed preference approach to agent
decision-making is problematic, then is it because of structural problems with
neoclassical economics itself or otherwise?
Samuelson and Revealed Preference Theory
I have sketched a
background to how Samuelson arrived at his operationally descriptivist approach
to economic theory. It is on this basis that he sought to establish
neoclassical theory on operationally descriptivist foundations. Consider
Samuelson’s reply to Fritz Machlup’s ‘Professor Samuelson on Theory and
Realism’ (Samuelson 1966:758-761): that the operationalist approach led to the
development of the revealed preference theory that provided ‘the most literal
example of a theory that has been stripped down to its bare implications for
empirical realism’ (765). Samuelson then claims that his 1938 paper proved that
the weak axiom of revealed preference showed that ‘the regular theory of
utility maximisation implied for the two-good case, no more and no less than
that “no two-observed points on the demand functions should ever reveal the
following contradiction of the Weak Axiom’”.
According to Samuelson
(1938), the purpose of his novel approach was to lead eventually to the
‘dropping of the last vestiges of the utility analysis.
This does not preclude the introduction of
utility by any who may care to do
84
so, nor will it
contradict the results attained by use of related constructs. It is merely that
the analysis can be carried out more directly and from a different set of
postulates’ (Samuelson 1966:4).
But what is of much
importance is the following: ‘All that follows shall relate to an idealised
individual – not necessarily, however, the rational homo-
economicus.
I assume in the beginning as
known, i.e., empirically determinable under ideal conditions, the amounts of n economic goods which will be purchased
per unit of time by an individual faced with the prices of these goods and with
a given total expenditure. It is assumed that prices are taken as given parameters
not subject to influence by the individual’ (Samuelson 1966:4).
The agent or economic
actor in this instance, according to Samuelson, is an ‘idealised individual’.
Assumedly what Samuelson means by this is that the agent as ‘idealised
individual’ behaves consistently and according to certain prescribed conditions
as already required for ordinal utility theory. These conditions as postulates
can be summarised as: i) the idealised agent’s demand functions are
single-valued in that the agent will always select the same basket of goods,
ii) the consumer’s demand functions are ‘all homogeneous of degree zero’(4),
i.e., ‘the consumer’s behaviour is independent of the units in which prices are
expressed’ (5). The third postulate states that ‘in any two price and income
situations and corresponding quantities of consumer’s goods’ the consumer
behaves consistently in that if some batch of goods X is chosen over another
batch Y, the consumer does not simultaneously choose Y over X.
In a later addendum (Samuelson
1938[b]:353-354) to his 1938 (a) paper, Samuelson then argues that postulates 1
and 2 are redundant because they are implied by the third postulate. In sum:
Samuelson’s theoretical goal is to achieve the same results of ordinal utility
theory without appeal to the psychologistic concept of utility.
Samuelson’s fundamental
postulate of RPT, known as the ‘weak axiom of revealed preference’ (WARP) is as
follows: for all pairs of items X0, X1
and a pair of
prices P0,P1, if X0 Rj X1 then not X1RjX0 where X0 Rj X1àP0X0e”P0X1
given income I0. This means that if some individual chooses one set of items
over a second set, he does not at the same time choose the second set over the
first set. This is the third postulate of Samuelson’s programme. As Samuelson
put it:‘Woe to any who deny any one of the three postulates here! For they are,
of course, deducible as theorems from the conventional analysis. They are less
restrictive than the usual set-up and logically equivalent to the reformulation
of Hicks and Allen’ (Samuelson
1966:12).
85
We recall that the conventional analysis requires 1) the
single-valuedness of demand functions, 2) homogeneity of degree zero of demand
functions, and 3) the negative semi-definiteness of the substitution matrix.
Samuelson was able to deduce this from his weak axiom of revealed preference.
But there would certainly be a problem in deriving the intended results if the agent’s
demand functions include the utility concept. The reason is that after all,
Samuelson’s WARP was designed to overcome the problem of utility.
It should be noted that
although Samuelson did not mention the term ‘revealed preference’ in his 1938
paper he does indeed use it in a subsequent
1948 paper wherein he attempts to derive
indifference curves from a set of revealed preference observations. But let us
return to Samuelson’s claim that the major results of the Hicks-Allen ordinal
theory approach could be deduced from the WARP.
There is an evident problematic here given that the agent
demand functions that confirmed ordinal utility theory themselves included
mentalist utilityengendering variables such as the subjective tastes of the
agent as consumer and advertiser. Subjective tastes determine the consumer’s
choice of items that are substitutes at the same price. It is also the tastes
of advertisers that seek to recommend choices among items that are similar in
price and quality. All this is evident from the formal demand function
expressed as Qx =A+BxPx where A stands for á (residual term) and Bx stands for
B1P1 + B2P2 + B3P3+…+BnPn. Thus when Samuelson claims that his third postulate
implies the demand functions of postulates 1 and 2, he must explain why such
demand functions can be differentiable without appealing to the subjective
concept of utility. Furthermore, it is difficult to see how those
differentiable demand functions could be effected without appealing to ‘an
increasing rate of marginal substitution’ which is exactly what Samuelson’s RPT
is devised
to avoid.
According to RPT only empirically observed behaviour
counts. Thus there is no need for hypothetical sets of single-valued and
homogeneous of order zero demand functions. How does Samuelson know what the
revealed preferences of any individual would be without actually witnessing
such. The overall problem here is that Samuelson’s novel discourse derives from
his idealised individual whom he did
not define in terms of his or her connection to real, empirically observable
individuals. This idealised individual is assumed to behave consistently and
conform to the choice paths required of postulates 1 and 2.Surely, this novel
discourse of Samuelson is hardly empiricist in approach.
In
his 1948 paper ‘Consumption Theory in Terms of Revealed Preference’
(Samuelson 1948:243-253) Samuelson
attempted to demonstrate that a further
86
conciliation could be
established between RPT – according to Samuelson shorn of ‘the last vestiges of
utility analysis’ – and ordinal utility theory by deriving indifference curves
from a set of revealed preference points for his idealised individual.
Samuelson begins his 1948 paper thus: ‘A decade ago I suggested that the
economic theory of consumer’s behaviour can be largely built up on the notion
of “revealed preference”. By comparing the costs of different combinations of
goods at different relative price situations, we can infer whether a given
batch of goods is preferred to another batch; the individual guinea pig, by his
market behaviour, reveals his preference pattern – if there is such a pattern’
(Samuelson 1966:64).
Samuelson’s goal in this paper
was to derive indifference curves for the set of choices or revealed
preferences that individual agents make. Note that
Samuelson’s effort in
this paper was to offer an alternative to Ian Little’s (1949) ‘ingenious proof
that if enough judiciously selected price-quantity situations are available for
two goods, we may define a locus which is the precise equivalent of the
conventional indifference curve’ (Samuelson
1966:64).
So it seems that we have come
full circle. Samuelson began his critique of ordinal theory with the intention
of ridding fundamental economic theory of its ‘last vestiges of the utility
analysis’ but still nostalgically attempted to show that the results of ordinal
theory could be derived from his postulates of revealed preference. Later in
his 1948 paper Samuelson attempted to show that agent indifference curves could
be derived from his postulates of revealed preference. The strategy here was to
build up a set of revealed preference points by way of the ‘Cauchy-Lipschitz
Process of Approximation’ ( Samuelson
1948:66), then join such
points in such a way that the agent’s indifference curves are ultimately
revealed. This approach offered a solution ‘indifference curve’ from below as Samuelson offered. Samuelson
complemented the
Cauchy-Lipschitz
approach with another approach that offered a mode of constructing indifference
curves from above (Samuelson
1948:69).
But all this is in vain and only
ends up compromising Samuelson’s original programme. The point is that if one
constructs an indifference curve from supposed revealed preferences that
coincides with those of ordinal utility theory, then one can explain the shape
of the resultant indifference curve only by appeal to the increasing rate of marginal substitution, which is exactly what
Samuelson sought to eliminate from consumer analysis in his 1938 paper.
According to standard ordinal utility theory, the increasing rate of marginal
substitution of some good X for Y (MRSxy), i.e. dy/dx equals
MUx/
MUy.,
i.e., the ratio of marginal utilities. So the concept of utility necessarily
enters the picture again once indifference curves that mirror those of ordinal
theory are introduced. The concordance with ordinal utility theory on the
87
part of Samuelson’s
attempt to construct indifference curves from the
theoretically revealed preference of
the idealised individual has led
theorists such as Houthakker (1950) to claim that Samuelson engaged in a
programmatic volte face when he attempted
to reintroduce ordinal theory into his 1947 and 1948 theorising.
What then is the problem? The problem, it would seem, is
that to attempt to explain and predict human decision-making simply by limiting
theory construction to observed choices of agents just would not work. Unless humans
are mindless – take this in the literal sense – robots we cannot hope to
explain human decision-making without appeal to empirically inaccessible
concepts such as reasons, motives, preferences, utility evaluations, and so on.
But this is a problem not only for neoclassical economics but also for other
sciences that deal with human behaviour such as psychology and history. In the
case of history, can the historian explain events without appeal to
nonempirical concepts such as reasons and motives?
Axiomatic Revealed Preference Theory
According to Axiomatic Revealed
Preference Theory, there are three basic axioms that purportedly describe and
explain choices: 1) the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (WARP), 2) the Strong
Axiom of Revealed Preference
(SARP) and 3)the Generalized Theory
of Revealed Preference (GARP, Sydney Afriat, 1976, The Combinatorial Theory of Demand). There are also a set of
preference relations that are operationally relevant. They are reflexivity,
transitivity, anti-symmetry, and completeness.
Assume the case of a
two-good choice schedule where some agent A is constrained in his choice of
items by an income I . Assume that A, given I, can purchase some Xi at time To
at prices Pi at time To. Assume too that if
A can purchase Xj at time T then Xj may
also be purchased at To. Therefore, for all Xj(i‘“j), if PiXie”PiXj then Xi is
revealed preferred Xj. This choice path of the individual agent may be
expressed as follows: XiRXja”PiXie”PiXj. We may extend this idea to include the
notion of indirect revealed preference. This means that Xi is indirectly
preferred to Xz if the two bundles are connected[C] by an indirect chain of
bundles. Thus Xi C Xj a”Xi C Xo, C…C, Xn C Xj.
Choice Axioms of Revealed Preference
Samuelson (1938) was
able to articulate his postulate of revealed preference only on the assumption
that his ‘idealised individual’ conforms to certain modes of decision-making.
Samuelson’s assumption was that his ‘idealised agent’ behaves consistently.
What this means for WARP, SARP and GARP is that the idealised agent’s choices should
conform to basic axioms of i)
88
reflexivity, ii)transitivity,
iii)completeness, and iv) acyclicity. These axioms are expressed according to
the following preference relations.
Reflexivity: (X)(X Rj X)
Transitivity: (X)(Y)(Z)[(X Rj Y Rj
Z!X Rj Z)] Completeness : (X)(Y)(X Rj Y v Y Rj X)
Acyclicity(antisymmetry)
: (X)(Y)(Z)[(X Rj Y Rj Z)‘“ Z Rj X
The upshot of all
this is that the idealised individual of RPT is required to conform to the
above set of axioms commonly referred to as the postulate of rationality as he
makes his choices according to the axioms of revealed preference theory.
What we have here then is a
neoclassical choice space populated by individuals without mental structures
who conform to certain programmatic rules. In other words, the neoclassical
agent of RPT is none other than a rational robot. But humans are much more than
rational robots programmed according to the postulate of rationality. Unlike
robots, when humans make choices or reveal their preferences they must appeal
to considerations of motive, reasons and utility, if their choices are to be
explained or understood by themselves and others.
The reason for this approach is
that genuine science seeks not only to describe phenomena but also to explain
them in terms of background theories with their constituent laws, postulates,
and axioms. The same must hold for those sciences that deal with human
behaviour. This explains why Samuelson had to augment his 1938(a) with a foray
into indifference curve analysis by way of a concatenation of revealed
preference points. The same observation may be applied to Samuelson’s 1950
paper, ‘The Problem of Integrability in Utility Theory’(Samuelson
1950:355-385). Even Houthakker, who formulated the SARP, noted that ordinal
theory when excised from neoclassical theory in Samuelson’s 1938 paper once
again became fundamental to that
theory(Houthakker
1983:63).
The point is that once Samuelson
agreed that RPT merely complemented ordinal theory and was not a replacement
for it, we were faced with a puzzling quandary. The question is as follows:
what then is the theoretical point of RPT if it merely complements ordinal
utility theory? The answer is that Samuelson believed that he was ridding agent
choice theory ofthe last vestiges of the
utility analysis. But this could not be the case given that both his
postulates 1 and 2 entailed by postulate 3 implicitly include utility analysis.
Differentiable demand functions make sense only when its agents make choices
explainable only by appeal to the utility concept. We have already
89
pointed out that Samuelson’s 1948
attempt to construct indifference curves from revealed preference points on a
budget line further compromised his position. Agent indifference curves can be
explained only by appeal to utility considerations.
The point of the above discussion is to
demonstrate that Samuelson actually
failed in his attempts to
establish agent choice theory – and by extension neoclassical economic theory –
founded only on the empirically observable choices of agents themselves.
Samuelson eventually had to reincorporate ordinal utility theory into his
analyses.
We recall that the key
actor in Samuelson’s choice theory programme is the idealised individual who is consistent in his or her choices and
conforms to certain axioms and postulates. Samuelson claims that this
idealised agent is ‘not necessarily, however, the rational homo-economicus’(Samuelson 1938[a]:4). But this ‘idealised
individual’ is necessarily ‘the rational homoeconomicus’.
Any idealised agent who behaves consistently and conforms to the theorist’s
idea of modelled behaviour is equivalent to a rational agent.
Revealed Preference Theory and its Aftermath
Samuleson’s total programme could be
summarised as consisting of three distinct papers: 1928(a), 1948, and 1950
(‘The Problem of Integrability in Utility Theory’). What is obvious is that
there are two distinct methodological approaches on the part of Samuelson. His
1938(a) paper was an attempt to replace ordinal utility theory with a strictly
operational RPT. But his 1948 paper reintroduced the idea of ordinal theory
when he tried to derive agents’ indifference curves from actual RPT points. The
result of this was to demonstrate a logical connection between RPT and ordinal
theory. In his 1950 paper, Samuelson tackled the so-called integrability
problem as it relates to ordinal theory. The goal was to demonstrate that
ordinal theory, as theory, entailed RPT as its empirical instantiation.
Samuelson recognised in his analyses that WARP did not offer a satisfactory
answer to the question of the empirical instantiation of ordinal theory. The
point was WARP was unable to deal with the issue of cyclic choices. The matter
was solved by Houthakker with his formulation of the strong axiom of revealed
preferences (SARP) which allowed only transitive inferences. We have again here
a reinforcing of the strict rationality assumptions of an augmented RPT. The
final statement by both Samuelson and Houthakker was that ordinal utility
theory was the theoretical
Infrastructure from which was derived an operational
RPT. With Houthakker’s SARP a logical equivalence was established between
ordinal utility theory and RPT.
90
One of the first
sustained critiques of Samuelson’s position is that of Stanley Wong (1978).
Wong’s key point against Samuelson is that Samuelson’s methodology founded on
‘descriptivism and operationalism is indefensible on logical and historical
grounds’(Wong 1978:127). Wong supports his critique on methodological grounds:
Samuelson’s methodology of descriptivism ‘ideally requires a theory to be
logically equivalent to its consequences’(Wong 1978:126). But for Wong
descriptivism is problematic because ‘a theory is not ideally equivalent to its
empirical consequences’(Wong
1978:126). And
the distinction between theoretical and observation terms on which the
equivalency of ordinal utility theory and RPT is founded cannot be maintained.
For Wong, ‘all observation terms are theory-laden’(Wong
1978:126). On
more prosaic grounds the issue is this: if ordinal utility theory and RPT are
logically equivalent hence interchangeable, then what is the point of RPT if
ordinal theory is just as operationally effective? Assuming that Wong’s
critique is valid, the main problem is that he does not offer an alternate
theory that would explain human economic decision-making.
Despite the problematic of
Samuelson’s revealed preference theory and the issue about which it was
developed and formulated there are theorists who think highly of it. Hal Varian,
for example, writes the following: ‘Samuelson’s 1938 theory of revealed
preference has turned out to be amazingly rich. Not only does the SARP provide
a necessary and sufficient condition for observed choices to be consistent with
utility maximisation, it also provides a very useful tool for empirical
nonparametric analysis of consumer choices’(Varian 2006:18, pre-publication
draft).Varian informs us in his paper that RPT is very much alive with his 2005
research on the prevalence of the theme yielding 997 articles.
The ultimate test of a scientific
theory is the quality of its predictions, i.e., do the theory’s predictions
conform to the theory. It is also a fact of scientific research that when a
theory makes successful predictions the proffered explanations for the
predicted phenomena gain in epistemological authority. In this connection, the
empirical results from testing the generalised version of RPT, i.e., GARP have
not been encouraging.
Till Grune (2004:396)),
for example, argues that empirical test results show that ‘after 66 years of
work, the preference framework and the maximization hypothesis still do not
have a firm empirical foundation’. Grune makes this claim because experiments
with human agents show ‘high violation rates’ of the axioms of RPT (Grune
2004:390). In support of his claim, he cites Reinhard Sippel (1997:1431-1444)
and Aurelio Mattei (2000:487-497) both of whom claim that the neoclassical
theory can be easily shown to be falsified on account of the large number of
agent violations.
91
According to Grune, the experimental test results,
controlled for time duration and price changes, show that according to
different experiments one quarter to two thirds of the test persons violated
GARP. In the experiments that tested for SARP violations (Sippel 1997) the
violation rate lay between 73 per cent and 90 per cent.
Thus the main problem is a theoretical one. A similar
argument has also been made by Daniel Kahneman and Richard Thaler
(2006:221-234). Clearly, SARP and GARP have been shown to be not always in
accordance with the actual choices of economic agents. It can also be argued
that the axiomatic requirements of completeness, transitivity, and
non-acyclicity are not shared by the three RPT axioms. WARP and GARP, as is
stated, do not preclude acyclic choices.
The crucial point at this juncture is that without
appeal to the agent’s preferences or subjective utility schedule, it would just
not be possible to determine how any agent arrived at making the choices he or
she did. A particular set of choices, ceteris
paribus, may conform to SARP but we would have no prima facie explanation of this conformity. Also, how would genuine
inferential errors or change of tastes, or just arbitrary decision-making be
detected if choices alone were available?
One might also consider cases of pondered indifference
between alternatives before choices were eventually made. There could also be
cases where choices were made on a whim or as a result of serious deliberation
that took into consideration new variables. There are also binary choice
situations in which both choices represent two sets of non-intersecting choice
criteria as in the case of the student who is conflicted between attending two
different universities for a set of entirely different reasons in each case.
This is clearly a situation in which there is no comparative preference basis
for decision-making.
It is for the above reasons that RPT, as originally
proposed by Samuelson and Houthakker, was seen as not adequate for a the
formulation of a complete theory of agent choice. What eventually had to occur
was the re-forging of links between empirically observable choices and ordinal
utility theory. As Samuelson himself (1972:256) put it in: ‘From the beginning
I was concerned to find out what refutable
hypotheses on the observable facts on price and quantity demanded were implied
by the assumption that the consumer spends his limited income at given prices
in order to maximize his ordinal utility’.
Choice and Preference
When the economist as social scientist
formulates theories he or she must necessarily begin with what is empirically
observable. And what is empirically observable are merely the choices that
individuals make. The choices that humans make are not random but based on
calculations and forethought in
92
most cases. In the case of economic
decision-making the economic agent first calculates his preferences among
alternatives and then effects a choice. It is this pre-choice set of mental
calculations that serves as the basis of ordinal utility. But the old problem
of how to quantify or to give an account of utility remains. Furthermore, given
that any proper scientific theory must offer explanations and predictions, the
question then is: how are explanations of agent behaviour possible without
appeal to mentalist concepts such as utility? This is the basis on which
Samuelson was forced to return to the theory of ordinal utility to allow for
the construction of explanatory theories of agent choice. But given that human
decision-making springs from nonaccessible human mental states, and given that
the choices individuals make may vary greatly even when the goals in question
are the same, neoclassical theory had no alternative but to posit an idealised homo economicus whose choice paths
constitute the basis on which neoclassical economic theory is constructed. The
question then was: what kind of conceptual framework would shape the behaviour
of the idealisedhomo economicus? This
conceptual framework was founded on the concept of rationality. But an appeal
to the concept of rationality, though leading to logically valid formal
structures, compromises the scientific tenor of neoclassical microeconomic
theory. What this yields is a theoretical structure that is necessarily
prescriptive.
Rationality
One of the
fundamental assumptions of neoclassical economic theory is that economic
agents, as empirical homologues of homo
economicus or
Samuelson’s
idealised individual, choose rationally. In theoretical terms this means
‘behaviour in accordance with the postulates of rationality’. Or more specifically,
the rational agent makes consistent choices whose goal is the optimisation of
some mathematical function. In the case of the individual agent as consumer, it
is the utility function that is maximised.
The postulate of rationality when
expressed in formal terms requires that the agent’s choices conform to the
completeness, reflexivity, and transitivity axioms. The agent is also required
to rank items according to rules of weak preference or strong preference. Thus
it is evident that the postulate of rationality is, indeed, a prescriptive
postulate according to which the economic agent must conform. In this regard,
the postulate of rationality is no different from, say, any concocted postulate
of goodness. A postulate of ‘goodness’ would be founded on the concept of an
ideally good individual who would make certain choices and decisions
consistently.
But just as with the postulate of
rationality, conformity to the postulate of goodness would witness many
deviations from the prescribed rule. Thus
93
contrary to the intent of the
founders of neoclassical economics, who wanted to establish a genuine science
of economics, the adoption of the rationality postulate as its central
theoretical plank compromises the whole enterprise. As theorist of economics,
Daniel Hausman, puts it: ‘Rationality is a normative notion concerning how
people ought to choose, prefer, or reason. So it may seem surprising that it
has a large role in positive economics, which is concerned with how people do
in fact choose. Since rationality is different from morality, it may also seem
surprising that rationality plays a large role in normative economics’ (Daniel
Hausman and Michael McPherson 1996:38).The truth is that whether for ‘positive’
or ‘normative’ economics, choice path rules that determine the prescribed
behaviour of agents must first be established. It is ‘rationality’ according to
the theorist that determines such rules – reflexivity, transitivity,
completeness, etc.
Despite the normative content of the foundational
postulate of rationality, neoclassical economic theory as expressed in
university textbooks and journal articles continues to maintain this normal
science paradigm despite evident predictive and explanatory anomalies. One way
to save the theory would be to collapse it into some kind of welfare economics
for the individual and for society as a whole. In this way, economics would be
viewed purely as a policy discipline whose function is to formulate theories of
how to increase human welfare singly or generally.
Yet neoclassical theorists would hardly want to countenance
such, given that their research paradigm is committed to the establishing a
scientific theory of human choice. But even if neoclassical economics were
reduced to a purely normative theory – as suggested above – there would still
be need to establish its structure on ontologically certifiable assumptions. A
basic assumption in this regard would be that individuals as decision-making
agents be constantly making economic choices. Another assumption would be that
individuals make their choices consciously and based on mentalist calculations.
Such mentalist calculations would also be explained in terms of psychological
concepts such as reasons and motives. This is where the methodological problem
confronted by neoclassical theory arises: how to offer a proper ontological
account of agent choice in terms of explanation and prediction. This is all
that the generic methodology of science demands.
On the Problematic of Rationality
The problem with the concept of
rationality is that despite its ontological status theorists of neoclassical
economics would seem to have no viable alternative. The result is there have
been ongoing attempts to salvage the concept on account of its crucial role in
neoclassical theory. Some theorists
94
have argued for a
kind of purely formalistic role played by the postulate of rationality (Boland
1981. Alexander Rosenberg (1976, 1992), on the other hand, takes issue with the
scientific tenor of neoclassical theory in terms of explanation and prediction –
the basic requirements for any genuine scientific theory. Rosenberg (1976),
first raises issues with the supposed causal laws of economics, and then
eventually comes to the conclusion that neoclassical microeconomics is a form
of applied mathematics (Rosenberg 1992).
Or consider Till Grune’s
(2004:396) comments that despite the fact that ‘after 66 years of work, the
preference framework and the maximization hypothesis still do not have a firm
empirical foundation. Hardcore empiricists might draw the consequence that
economics is therefore not a science at all’. Grune’s recommendation is
noteworthy: ‘Instead, economists should admit that their science operates with
theoretical concepts, which never can be fully defined on terms of observable
parameters. Such an admission would leave economics in good company. The
concept of the gene in biology, and the concept of the inter-atomic bond in
chemistry are of similar type, and few deride these sciences for operating with
them’(Grune 2004:396)
One must take issue with Grune’s claim here though. Grune
is in error to argue that the theoretical concepts of neoclassical economics
are on par with those of the physical and biological sciences. The fact is that
while the gene and the inter-atomic bond possess real empirical content this is
not the case with the concept of rationality. Like ‘goodness’, rationality is
not a natural attribute of any empirical phenomenon.
On Bounded Rationality
The problematic
of rationality is further instanced by the fact that it has been long
established in practice that ‘rational economic man’, the central actor in neoclassical
economic theory, represents no more than a formal idealisation of economic
decision-making. This understanding of economic decisionmaking was developed by
Herbert Simon in a set of papers that comprehensively sought to replace the
behaviour of homo economicus of the
classical model with that of an agent whose decision-making options were
constrained by lack of full knowledge of the economic environment. In other words,
rationality under such constraints are ‘bounded’ and all the agent can hope for
is ‘satisficing’ (Simon 1955, 1959, 1982). Consider Simon’s approach to the
problem: ‘Broadly stated, the task is to replace the global rationality of economic
man with a kind of rational behaviour that is compatible with the access to
information and the computational capacities that are actually possessed by
organisms, including man, in the kinds of environments in which such organisms
exist’ (Simon 1955:99). This leads to Simon’s
95
observation that defined rational
behaviour should not be seen only as substantive rationality but also as
procedural rationality which greatly extends the empirical foundations of
neoclassical economics (Simon 1986:212).
Simon’s basis for this attempt to transform neoclassical
economics into a more empirically grounded discipline is that its predictive,
and hence explanatory, record has not been encouraging. Simon’s thesis deserves
much consideration given that his step-by-step approach to decision-making has
become central to game theory and other decision theory areas.
But it is exactly at this point that
Simon’s programme encounters a
problem. The attempt to redirect economic
theory from the formal neoclassical model of rational choice to one founded on
the principle of procedural rationality and the actual psychology of human
decision-making encounters the same problem that Simon underscores with
standard neoclassical theory. The reason is that human behaviour is quite
complex and attempts to explain and predict decision-making from the standpoint
of psychology would tend to compound the issue further. Thus how should one
explain what the theorist as observer would describe as decidedly irrational
behaviour; or behaviour that accepted the theorist’s definition of rationality
but was consistently
irrational in terms of committed errors?
Given that the standards of rationality that agents adhere
to derive maximally from their learning environments, as opposed to being the
results of instinctual promptings, Simon’s programme reduces to the standard
neoclassical theory, Simon’s theory of satisficing would seem to be none other
than the classical agent making choices under particular constraints. But the
goal is still the maximisation of expected utility. So what then is one to make
of Simon’s claim that economics without recourse to empirically based
psychological and sociological research is ‘a one-bladed scissors’?
The point is that despite a plea for an economics reliant
more on empirically observed agent choice than on theoretical formalism, Simon
must still seek recourse to the postulate of rationality if his theories are to
have any semblance of explanatory and predictive power. After all, whenever any
agent effects a choice there must be prior moments of deliberation according to
some normative schedule. But given that matters are compounded by the fact that
individuals may vary in terms of their schedules of rationality and that they
are prone to errors, bounded rationalists such as Simon are faced with a
formidable task – that of constructing separate rationality schedules for each
agent.
But Simon’s programme is preferable to that of standard
neoclassical economics because it recognizes that economics cannot define
itself as an empirical science unless it has its theoretical foundations based
in the empirical
96
world and not on
the decision-making of an idealised rational economic man. Simon has approached
the problem in the correct way but success is unlikely given the enormity of
the empirical logistics involved.
This may be the reason
why theorists of formal economics have done little to replace the construct of
rational economic man with that of the agent as a cognitively fallible
decision-maker who can only ‘satisfice’ on grounds of his or her ‘bounded
rationality’. Human behaviour is much too complex
and motive-driven
to be dynamically plotted according to some pre-established programme of
decision-making. This approach is well summarised by Esther Sent as follows:
‘In economics, Simon has become mostly known for his razor-sharp criticism of
the rationality postulate. In particular he criticized the four basic
assumptions of neoclassical economics’ (Sent 2004:313). According to Sent,
Simon argued that ‘the mind functions mostly by applying approximate solutions
to problems’(Sent 2004:313). Thus humans in their decision-making adopt
‘satisficing strategies’ rather than conform to some ‘maximisation of utility function’(Sent
2004:313). But because it is much more difficult to construct such satisficing
strategies for separate individuals, the continuing orthodoxy among economists
is to model economic decisionmaking as if it were some form of mathematical
logic.
According to Ariel
Rubinstein, who has adopted Simon’s paradigm of bounded rationality, the
purpose of economic models are as follows: ‘Models of economic theory are
meant to establish “linkages” between the concepts and statements that appear
in our daily thinking on economic situations’ (Rubinstein 1998:191). Rubinstein
contrasts this with what he perceives as Simon’s idea that economics should aim
at creating predictive models founded on testable empirical evidence
(Rubinstein 1998:191). Yet as was pointed out above, Simon’s more
empirically-minded approach would still be at loss to formulate theories of
agent decision-making without first establishing some normative framework from
which the economist who embraces the satisficing paradigm would operate.
Vanberg’s Evolutionary
Rationality
Viktor Vanberg
(2004) argues that the rationality postulate may be salvaged by regarding it as
‘an alternative evolutionary outlook
at purposeful human action that, as I suppose, captures much of what appears to
make the rationality postulate so attractive to economists but allows one to
escape the ambiguities that have notoriously plagued the rationality postulate’
(Vanberg
2004:2).Vanberg begins
his critique with the observation that the rationality idea could be divided into
what he refers to as the ‘rationality principle’ and the ‘rationality
hypothesis’. The rationality principle for Vanberg merely states that all human
action is rational in the sense that it is purposeful. This is the
97
definition of
rationality that was proposed by Ludwig von Mises (1949) in his praxeological
approach to economics. But as Vanberg would state: ‘the rationality principle
by itself cannot serve as the fundamental behavioural conjecture of an
explanatory, empirically contentful theory’ (Vanberg 2004:3). In this regard, the
rationality principle may be regarded only as ‘a definitional statement or as a
heuristic device’(Vanberg 2004:3) Thus the rationality principle may be useful
but problematic on account of its lacking in empirical content. ‘Only by adding
additional refutable assumptions can one turn the rationality principle into an
empirically contentful hypothesis’ (Vanberg 2004:3-4).
According to Vanberg, ‘rationality’ as applied to
empirically refutable hypotheses in the sense of making global and empirical
claims about the choices of agents, suffers from a disconnect between theory
and empirical results. This is the case with the well known maximisation
hypothesis which ‘is in such apparent conflict with behavioural reality that it
is rarely ever claimed to be descriptive of actual human behaviour’ (Vanberg
2004:4).
There have been
noteworthy attempts on the part of theorists such as Gary Becker (1976), who
attempts to explain all of human behaviour in terms of what seems like a
version of the rationality principle but applicable to human behaviour in terms
of income and price effects rather than subjective tastes. Vanberg, however, points
out that this global approach to human economic agency does not alter the fact
that Becker’s ‘economic or rational choice approach to behaviour’ is founded
‘on no more than the heuristic rationality principle’ (Vanberg 2004:7). Vanberg
concludes his commentary on Becker with the observation that Becker’s
‘assumption of individual rationality…is specified in a way that makes it
indistinguishable from the empirically rationality principle’ (Vanberg 2004:7).
Given the evident problematic with the orthodox rationality
model as an acceptable explanation of human decision-making, neoclassical
economists still persist in its application. As Vanberg puts it: ‘Even if they
are not entirely happy with their rationality, to them there is no really
attractive alternative in sight’ (Vanberg 2004:10).
Vanberg rejects the idea
that there are no viable alternatives and proposes what he refers to as an
‘evolutionary outlook at human behaviour’ in the form of ‘the paradigm of
program-based behaviour’ adapted from biologist Ernst Mayer’s thesis that
‘intentional, goal-or-purpose-seeking behaviour can be viewed as guided by
programs or instructions encoded in the
agent for what to do (or not to do) in certain types of situation’ (Vanberg
2004:11).
What this evolutionary approach achieves is
as follows: the paradigm of program-based behaviour appeals to the concept of
rationality to explain behaviour that is based on agents engaging in purposeful
action that is constantly seeking to adapt to the conditions of the environment.
What we
98
have here is a
kind of rational or purposeful decision-making that proceeds according to the
principle of repeated trials when intended goals are not achieved.
Vanberg amplifies his evolutionary theory
of adaptive decision-making by
further appeal to J.H.
Holland’s (1992a) theory of rule-based adaptive agents.
According to this theory,
agents made decisions on a kind of iterative feedback process based on ‘rules
that anticipate the consequences of certain responses’(Vanberg 2004:13). These
rules serve as ‘internal models’ that may be tacit or overt. Tacit models
behave according to the principle of autonomous stimulus and response, as in
the case of, say, a ‘bacterium that “moves in the direction of a chemical
gradient implicitly predicting that food lies in that direction”’ (Vanberg
2004:13). On the other hand, Vanberg informs us, Holland’s ‘overt internal
models inform the kind of deliberative choices on which rational choice
accounts tend to focus’ (Vanberg 2004:14).
Vanburg further
explicates Holland’s adaptive learning approach by pointing to his ‘bucket
brigade algorithm’ which appeals to induction that ‘makes a task manageable
that otherwise would surely be beyond the capacity of boundedly rational
agents, namely the task of keeping track of the success record of a complex
repertoire of rules that are activated, in varying combinations, as components
of internal models of current problem situations’
(Vanberg 2004:15). A key
point cited by Vanberg that he adopts from Holland is as follows: ‘for complex
adaptive systems in general and, in particular, for markets that are composed
of intelligent, learning human beings “there is no way to predict the overall
behaviour by looking at the behaviour of an average
individual’” (Vanberg 2004:16). The solution is to adopt the ‘paradigm of
program-based’ behaviour.
Despite the evidence of what
actually occurs, economists still appeal to the principle of perfect
rationality because it offers an explanation of how markets ostensibly operate.
As Vanburg puts it: ‘the assumption of perfect rationality is, from this
perspective, not so much a conjecture about the cognitive and calculative
capabilities of human beings per se,
but a conjecture about the working properties of markets as social
arrangements’ (Vanberg
2004:17).
On this basis those who
win in the market game are rational choice makers who have effected choices in
conformity with the idea of perfect rationality. Vanberg’s response to this is
that this limited theory of goal directed decision – making is inadequate even
when expressed as the ‘rational expectations’ theory of R.A. Lucas. The
‘rational expectations’ theory is evidently then just another form of the
feedback-adaptive model of Holland’s already discussed by Vanberg. According to
Lucas, as cited by Vanburg, economics
99
consists of a set of
decision rules that are ‘steady states of some adaptive process, decision rules
that are found to work over a a range of situations and hence are no longer
revised appreciably as more experience accumulates’
(Vanberg 2004:20-21).
Vanberg, however, does not see this as a solution given the
extended range of the rationality principle as it has been adopted by other
areas in economics and the other social sciences. Vanberg argues that ‘such
self limitation would clearly be in conflict not only with the ambition of
modern approaches in economics that – like public choice, the new institutional
economics, law and economics and others – seek to extend the economic approach
beyond the study of market behaviour, it would also conflict with ambitions to
understand the innovative creative dynamics of market processes’
(Vanberg 2004:21).
The point
Vanberg makes is that economic theory ought to adopt a ‘more common behavioural
paradigm’ to handle the general social phenomena and behaviours that the social
sciences in general deal with. But Vanberg’s more comprehensive goals may be
overly optimistic here given the methodological problems that some researchers
in areas such as political science encounter.Consider the following from Green
and Shapiro (1994:9): ‘Furthermore, rational choice hypotheses are too often
formulated in ways that are inherently resistant to genuine empirical testing,
raising serious questions about whether rational choice scholarship can
properly be regarded as social science’. Green and Shapiro are political
scientists and their conclusion concerning the relevance of the neoclassical
model to social science as a whole is as follows: ‘Our central argument in this
book has been that empirical applications of rational choice theory in
political science since the 1960s have been marred by a syndrome of
methodological shortcomings’
(Green and Shapiro
1994:202). These shortcomings derive from the attempt to develop a ‘universal
theory of politics and the belief that anything less cannot aspire to be
genuine science’ (Green and Shapiro 1994:202). What Green and Shapiro claim to
have demonstrated is: ‘we have shown in this book, however, that to date no
empirically credible universal theory has been developed by proponents of
rational choice’ (Green and Shapiro
1994:202).
So despite Vanberg’s novel
sociological approach to the issue of economic
decision-making by way of theorists
such as Holland, the issue of the scientific status of neoclassical economics
still remains. Vanberg does not offer any formulation of what ‘a more complex
behavioural paradigm’ might be. He has proposed a more evolutionary principle
of rationality as a way of overcoming the problematic of the testable
rationality hypothesis.
100
But the old problem of
formulating adequate behavioural functions that would describe, explain and
predict the individual choices of agents still remains.Given that the ultimate
goal of scientific theory is explanation, the neoclassical theorist is faced
with a dilemma: two individuals may effect the same choice but for entirely
different reasons. The only other alternative, for explanatory reasons, is to
assume that human agents are mindless robots.
Vanberg’s theory is interesting
in that he seeks to broaden the application of rationality to apply to areas
other than neoclassical economics. But his ‘evolutionary’ approach though
useful in helping to understand decisionmaking both in the market and
otherwise, ought not to be considered a scientific theory at all but a
heuristic that allows the theorist to interpret intra-cultural rules of
rationality once the rules of contextually rational behaviour are known. The
problem here though is that the intra-contextual rules of rationality are all
learned within a cultural context. And they are all prescriptive rules. Such
rules, if broken, deliberately or through cognitive error, often lead to
penalties imposed by the market. It is for the above reasons that I am inclined
to believe that neoclassical economics is essentially a branch of ethical
theory.
In what follows I will seek to first to demonstrate that
neoclassical microeconomics founded on the postulate of rationality is a
special case of welfare economics which is generally recognised as the
normative and evaluative side of neoclassical economics. I will then argue that
the optimal way to interpret economic theory is to regard it as a system of
ethics in the form of rule utilitarianism.
Neoclassical Theory as a Special Case of Welfare
Economics
Welfare economics
is generally viewed as the normative side of neoclassical economics given that
economic decision-making, in this instance, is determined according to its
normative implications. But an analysis of the theoretical structure of welfare
economics would inform us that its axiomatic and preference relations structure
is identically that of positive neoclassical theory. If that is the case then
it logically follows that positive neoclassical theory is itself a normative
theory whose social welfare function consists of the neoclassical theorist
him/herself and all agents.
First, we should note that the
social welfare functions of welfare economics satisfy the properties of
completeness, transitivity, and reflexivity which are applicable to weak
ranking (R), strong ranking (P), and indifference (I). But the problematic
concerning the interpersonal comparisons of utility rejected by many theorists
was seen to be resolved by Kenneth Arrow’s
Possibility Theorem
(Arrow 1951). Arrow’s Possibility Theorem states that
101
if interpersonal and dictatorial choices
are excluded then no universal social ranking is possible. Arrow’s theorem
rests on five conditions which are incompatible with any social ranking, R.
It is on the basis of Arrow’s theorem that orthodox
welfare economics theory derives from the principle of Pareto optimality the
following: the equilibrium optimal state of the welfare economy is that at
least one agent is better off than in any other state.
What is significant for the present discussion is that
neoclassical theory is seen to demonstrate a consistent equivalence between a
competitive general equilibrium and Pareto optimality. This amounts to the
following: 1) every equilibrium position of the economy is a Pareto optimal
state, and 2) any Pareto optimal state
of the economy is an equilibrium position of the economy.
The meaning of this is as follows: 1) the axiomatic
equivalence of positive neoclassical economics and normative welfare economics
means that positive neoclassical economics rests on the same normative
foundations as welfare economics. After all, there is the consensus that
welfare economics constitutes the normative side of neoclassical economics. We
must conclude, therefore, that neoclassical economic theory founded on the
postulate of rationality is a special case of normative welfare economic
theory.
Neoclassical Economics and Utilitarian Ethics
In this section I want to argue that the
most accurate description of neoclassical economic theory in its positive mode,
founded as it is on the postulate of rationality, constitutes an aspect of
utilitarianism, that is, rule utilitarianism. In the standard literature, it is
claimed that although ethical considerations played an important role
historically when it was known as political economy, such has not been the case
when economics decided to assume scientific status. Thus contemporary theorists
speak not of economics possessing ethical content but rather needing a closer
relationship with ethics. In this regard, one might consider the works of Sen
(1987), Hausman and McPherson (1996) and Groenewegen (1996).
But it should be noted that in the past, economics
and ethics were both intertwined, to the extent that economics was seen as a
subsection of ethics. As A.W. Coats notes: “Nineteenth century and twentieth
century economics was, of course, a direct
outgrowth of moral philosophy, and within that framework many authors
would move unselfconsciously back and forth between positive (is) and normative
(ought) statements without uneasiness and further specification’ (Coats
1996:81-82).
The definitive rupture between positive economics and
normative economics took place when J.M. Keynes proclaimed that positive
economics
102
as a positive
science deserved to establish itself independently as a genuine science (See
Michael V. White 1996:104). The same applies to Alfred Marshall. Michael White
writes: ‘Like Keynes, Marshall wanted to separate economics from any particular
philosophical or ethical system’ White 1996:106). I want to demonstrate now
that neoclassical economic theory, despite attempts to the contrary, is indeed
an aspect of utilitarianism, that is, rule utilitarianism.
Before making the case for
neoclassical economics as an instance of rule utilitarianism, it would be
instructive to demonstrate how modern neoclassical economics was developed from
the assumptions of classic utilitarianism. It was Bentham who first formulated
the idea that ethical theory should be founded on the twin sensate principles
of pain and pleasure. The idea here is that humans are wont to define the
natural language concepts of good and bad in terms of pleasure and pain, both
psychological and physical. It is for this reason that explanation of the
behaviours of humans is more appropriately arrived at by appeal to
utilitarianism rather than to deontology. This idea is echoed in Jeremy
Bentham’s 1879) observation that human conduct is determined principally by the
‘two sovereign masters of pleasure and pain’. This was the basis for Bentham’s
‘felicific calculus’founded on the principle of ‘utility’. But what was quite
important for Bentham’s thesis and a
subsequent
quantitative economics was that the utility derived from specific acts was
measurable in terms of intensity, duration, propinquity, remoteness, and so on.
These considerations were captured by the measurable concept of the util,
central to the concept of cardinal utility.
Within the context of
post-Benthamite economics, it is instructive to note that the original idea of
evaluating human decision-making – strictly moral or otherwise – in terms of
pleasure or pain, ultimately to be understood as ‘satisfaction’, became
translated into the measurable metric of ‘cardinal utility’.
The principle
here is that satisfaction could be measured and that it was variable over time.
This explains the later introduction of concepts such as ‘marginal utility’
into the mechanics of a developing neoclassical economics.
But the utilitarian paradigm was stymied by
the fact that cardinal utility
could not be
measured because ‘satisfaction’ could only be determined subjectively. There
was no measuring rod available that could measure comparatively the
satisfaction that individuals experienced as they made their decisions. This
problem also led to the observation that interpersonal comparisons of utility
were not possible. One recalls in this connexion J.S. Mill’s quip that the
‘dissatisfaction’ experienced by a Socrates was of greater utilitarian value
qualitatively than ‘satisfaction’ experienced by a – pig. Well, who knows? The
upshot of this was that the utilities that agents derived from their decisions
were individual and subjective, thereby raising questions
103
as to whether utilitarianism as an
ethical theory could ever be established. If the ‘the good’ was determined by
some felicific calculus which in turn was restricted to non-comparable
subjective sensations of pleasure and pain then there would be no firm basis
for a general theory of utilitarianism. I discuss this on the grounds that the
utilitarian principle, which states that the optimal state of affairs for
society is one in which the sum of all possible individual welfare
(satisfaction) functions is maximal, is central to modern welfare economics.
But the central point I make in the above discussion is
that there is a very evident connexion between neoclassical economics and the
theory of ethics known as utilitarianism. In fact, it could be argued that
neoclassical economics is a direct product of utilitarianism as a system of
ethics.
Rule and Act Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism is defined as the
ethical theory founded on the principle that preferable acts are those that
increase rather than diminish the satisfaction, welfare or sensate well-being
of individuals taken singly or collectively. Utilitarianism has also been
defined as an instance of the broader ethical theory known as consequentialism
whose definitional principle is that the ethical value of an act is to be
determined only by its consequences. One might, in this regard, contrast
consequentialist theory with deontological theory which argues that the moral
worth of a decision or act is determined purely by its intrinsic rightness or
wrongness. What is interesting though is that in the realm of public affairs
human agents prefer to evaluate the moral worth of a decision or act according
to some version of utilitarian consequentialism. The determinant invariably
reduces to whether the decision or act enhances agent welfare or not. It is at
this point that the connection between utilitarianism and neoclassical
economics becomes evident. The question then is as follows: when theorists of
neoclassical economics formulate theories according to the fundamental
postulate of rationality, which is instantiated as the maximization of expected
utility, to what end or consequences should the decision-making neoclassical
agent maximize expected utility? The obvious answer is that the maximization of
expected utility is expected to increase the welfare of the decision-making
agent. In this regard, the neoclassical theorist is in reality formulating
ethical dictates according to consequential utilitarianism.
Thus the prescriptive principle of neoclassical
theory, according to the postulate of rationality, could be viewed as an
instance of rule utilitarianism. Rule utilitarianism is defined as a kind of
regulative principle of utilitarian conduct that states that the agent should
make choices that enhance his or
104
her own welfare.
Apply this ethical principle to all agents as is prescribed by neoclassical
theory and neoclassical theory logically entails welfare economics, the
normative branch of neoclassical economics.
But there are cases where the
agent in actual circumstances seeks to maximize utility according to the formal
principle of rationality but is constrained because of cognitive limitations
with regard to information, cogitating skills and contingent events. Under such
circumstances the agent would be required to act according to minimax rules.
One recalls in this instance Herbert Simon’s theory of bounded rationality
according to which agents must act to maximize expected utility in specific
situations constrained by available resources and knowledge.
I have argued above that
neoclassical economics on account of its reliance on the principle of utility
is fundamentally an aspect of the theory of ethics known as utilitarianism.
According to ethical theory ‘the good’ is what is usually defined as an act or
thing that is desirable or preferred either in terms of intrinsic or
deontological worth or in terms of its sensate consequences. In this regard,
neoclassical theory is not more than a formal instance of rule utilitarianism.
In fact, the rule utilitarianism of neoclassical microeconomics could best be categorised
as an example of ‘preference utilitarianism’. Thus the good consequences of any
choice would be classified as ‘preference satisfaction’.
It follows that when the neoclassical agent
is required to be consistent in his or her choices so as to maximize expected
utility, the theorist is merely formulating an ethical theory founded on the
idea of preference utilitarianism.
Excursions into Fantasy: Behavioural Economics
and Neuroeconomics
Given the inadequacies
of neoclassical theory in terms of its capacity as science to explain and
predict in conjunction with its reliance on the problematic postulate of
rationality, there have been some new theoretical efforts to deal with its
problems. The most influential of these new approaches are behavioural
economics and its correlate neuroeconomics. It will be shown that both
paradigms are incapable of solving the problematic of neoclassical economics.
Behavioural economics begins with
the assumption that economic agents do not always conform to the postulate of
rationality according to its optimisation rules. The solution for the
behavioural economist is to bring psychology back into economics. According to
Colin Camerer: ‘In fact, behavioural economics represents a reunification of
psychology and economics, rather than a brand new synthesis, because early
thinking about economics was shot through with psychological insight’ (Camerer
1999:1057).
This
reunification has its foundations in the earlier research in psychology carried
out conjointly by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (1979.
105
Noteworthy contributors to the behavioural
paradigm include earlier theorists in game theory such as von Neumann and
Morgenstern (1944).More recently, the research efforts of Richard Thaler (1992)
and Dan Ariely (2008) are to be noted. As stated above, the impetus behind
behavioural economics is the fact that individuals often behave differently
from what is prescribed by orthodox neoclassical theory.
Behavioural economics chooses to remedy that problem with
an emphasis on laboratory-bound empirical work. It has been variously observed
that human behaviour is multifaceted and comes in a multiplicity of dimensions.
There are risk takers, risk averters, present bias agents, future bias agents,
individuals who deliberately choose not to maximise their utilities in
empirical terms, etc. But despite this effort by theorists such as Ariely
(2008), behavioural economics is ultimately compromised by its insistence that
agents make mistakes when they do not conform to the optimising mechanism as
suggested by the postulate of rationality. The fact is that the construction of
scientific theory is based on the assumption that nature behaves predictably.
This is what allows the formulation of scientific laws and the construction of
theories that determine prediction and explanation, crucial for scientific
understanding.
In the case of human beings, however, driven as they are by
consciously subjective thought, there is little basis to establish universal
laws of choice. Were human behaviour driven by instinct, things would be a bit
more tractable. The point is that as long as human choice is consciously
subjective and at variance and not fully predictable then new approaches as in
the case of behavioural economics are bound to be theoretically suspect.
Matters are compounded by the fact that it seems impossible to dispense with
some postulate of rationality if explanatory theories are going to be
constructed. After all, humans make conscious choices founded on consciously
engendered reasons and motives. It would be a different matter entirely if
human choice did not have that mysterious mental correlate that in turn has its
correlate in neuronic activity. The upshot of all this is that given the great
complexity and range of human thought in terms of reasons for choices and the
choices themselves, the behavioural theorist is confronted with an enormous
problem given that any conception or postulate of rationality is just as good
as any other. So the only kind of theories that the behavioural economist could
formulate would be his or her preferred theories, founded on his or her notions
of rationality.
Such notions of rationality employed by the theorist would
often be more cognitively robust than those employed by live agents themselves.
But it would then be the epistemological responsibility of the theorist to
explain the psychological basis for the behavioural phenomena of agent
cogitation on
106
decisions that
include degrees of riskiness ( the “prospect theory” of Kahneman and Tversky,
1979) and “framing” ( agents prefer the same results expressed positively
rather than negatively according to test results of Kahneman and Tversky,
1979). It is on this comparative basis that behavioural economics is able to
play off the standard rationality paradigm of neoclassical economics with
deviant models founded on empirical behaviour. Thus all we can say in all of
this is that in behavioural economics the orthodox rationalitybased models
still stand and they justify themselves in terms of their being more
cognitively robust than the deviant empirical models founded on actual agent
decision-making. Similar considerations apply to the research done on animal behaviour
as a way of showing that animals do conform to the orthodox postulate of
rationality as if to confirm implicitly that humans and animals are hard-wired
with the orthodox rationality postulate
But this is not the issue. After
all, a robot can be programmed to make rationally optimal moves in any kind of
game scenario, whether chess, for example, or otherwise. The issue has to do
with explaining the myriad kinds of decisions agents consciously make as they
pursue goals by whatever chosen means. But when such decisions are consciously
made, explanations require an appeal to particular models of agent rationality.
In other words ‘rationality’ necessarily applies to humans for explanatory
purposes but not to animals or robots. Behavioural economics is useful in that
it widens the empirical scope of neoclassical economics but that just
complicates matters more. Neoclassical economics is thereby committed not just
to one model of rationality but to a multiplicity of others.
Given that normal human decision-making
is usually effected consciously, empirically-minded behavioural economics deems
it necessary to seek ultimate explanation of agent behaviour in terms of the
neuronic basis of decisionmaking. This is the basis for the branch of
behavioural economics known as neuroeconomics. Research has been done to match
behavioural choices according to positive or negative agent appraisals by
machine inspection of brain activity (Sanfey et al 2003; Camerer et al 2005). But all this is overly optimistic
thinking as researchers in neuroscience and philosophy will note. There seems
to be that seemingly impassable gap between subjective mental states and their
neuronsic correlates. Behavioural economics hardly has new insights into this
matter. The conclusion here is that neoclassical economics has been pursuing a
pipe dream in its quest for scientific authenticity and respectability. Based
on the analysis above, it is evident that neoclassical economics is not much
more than a normative guide to optimal decisionmaking. But a guide that few
agents are capable of conforming to either voluntarily or otherwise.
107
Neoclassical Economics as Ideology
We have seen that modern economics
has been persistent in its attempt to be classified as a positive science, a
kind of engineering-like description of human decision-making. This is a point
aptly made by Sen (1987:4). It is this engineering approach that has
characterised all aspects of neoclassical theory for the last several decades.
Even the normative side of welfare economics is assumed by many theorists to be
on the same value-free plane as positive economics. This is guaranteed by the
equilibrium compatibility between general equilibrium theory and the Paretian
welfare principle. In this regard, neoclassical economics is concerned mainly
with questions of efficiency and rarely those of equity. And even in those
cases where equity considerations enter the picture, such is compromised by the
constraints of the Pareto principle. This means that a Paretian welfare
economics offers little guidance in situations of extreme disparities in
wealth.
The market is the locus of operation for all of
neoclassical economics. It is the habitat of rational economic man whose
decisions are meaningful only under considerations of efficiency. Thus
decisions that seem to affront human well-being and welfare are preferable as
long as they yield efficiency results. The trained neoclassical economist is to
be seen therefore as the kind of physician who is tied to profit-seeking
insurance companies and who seeks first not to offer his patient optimal care
but to cut costs – often at the
expense of life and limb.
Evidently, neoclassical economics has taken flight from the
real world to install itself in a universe of humanoid automatons programmed
according to a prescribed postulate of rationality. In this fictitious universe
the theoreticians are free to concoct as many models as they fancifully choose.
The truth is that we live in the world of real humans whose decision-making
abilities are subject to their limitations in knowledge and cognitive
dispositions. But the theoretical and applied practitioners in the field of
economics all know that the mantra of ‘efficiency’ rules in both the artificial
and the real world. Thus the real world of humans is constantly being assailed
with the slogans of
‘cost cutting’, ‘down sizing’,
‘maximization of profits’, and so on. If ‘efficiency’ requires massive
unemployment then so be it. The counterargument usually employed by the
theorist is that the economy is best left to operate according to the laws of
the market and the rational expectations of agents. But I have shown above that
neoclassical economic theory is intrinsically value-laden and an instance of
preference utilitarianism.
An ideology is a structured set of beliefs that is in
reality value-laden but presents itself as an objective set of ideas and facts
about how the world is structured. So it is that the whole structure of
neoclassical economics 108 represents an ideology. Neoclassical economics is
indeed the ideology of the age as argued for by Yanis Varoufakis (1996) in his
paper ‘O Tempora, O Mores! Economics as the Ethos of Our Times’. Successful
ideologies become a pervasive aspect of society despite the fact that they may
affect different persons differentially. The foundational ideology of
neoclassical economics has been so successful that even those negatively
affected by its ethos support it. Its ethos of individual maximization of
utility and gain produces unemployment, poverty, exploitation, the fetish of
the cash nexus, huge disparities in wealth, and the evaluation of individuals
according to their ownership of material objects.
In more sociological terms neoclassical economics serves as
the theoretical substructure of the ideological system that promotes
neo-liberal market economics in today’s world. The structure of the world it
promotes is premised on the theory that the market system is founded on the
objective laws and principles formulated by neoclassical economics. Individual
agency is objective normalcy, hence the sloganeering dictate that the
privatization of capital is preferable to government-based spending on the
social and welfare needs of society as a whole. In brief, the generic
neoclassical economics sees nothing wrong with societies with large Gini
coefficient disparities.
Shifting the Paradigm: From Economics to
Anthropology
In their attempts
to establish economics as an empirical science theorists of economics were
required to formulate theories that were both predictive and explanatory. But
this goal was unachievable for two main reasons: 1) human behaviour is
unpredictable and 2) the sources of human behaviour – necessary for explanatory
purposes – are non-empirical mental states. The heuristic solution was to
formulate a model founded on the theoretical template of a rational economic
man who would be the basis for all of formal and empirical economic theory. But
as Herbert Simon pointed out many decades ago, that model proved itself to be
both empirically and theoretically unworkable. Simon’s replacement model,
founded on the principle of bounded rationality itself, proved to be unviable,
hence the continuing reliance on the formal analytic model of neoclassical
economics. In this regard, ‘economic models are viewed as being analogous to
models in mathematical logic’ (Rubenstein
1998:191).
There are problems with this
approach given that the understanding of the empirical decisions that humans
make in the context of economics is what is required of any avowedly empirical
discipline. One solution to this problem is to apply the same methodology that
scientific researchers employ when they study the behaviour of animals and
humans from a purely empirical standpoint.
109
Ethologists inform us on the behaviours of animals such as
mammals that engage in exactly the same kind of behaviours that humans engage
in: employing the behavioral mechanisms appropriate for survival within
particular ecological environments. Thus one would not be in error to state
that ethology offers explanations and predictions concerning the economic life
of, say, elephants in some specific ecological environment. Given the fact that
the choices that mammals effect are much more instinct-driven than those of
humans, the ethologist can offer explanations that are sufficiently cognitively
satisfying without recourse to the theoretical machinery of neoclassical
economics.
So it is too
for the anthropologist who studies the economic decisions of humans in
environments that do fall under the sway of neoclassical economics. Empirically
descriptive models are all that the anthropologist needs to explain and even
predict how economic transactions eventuate in some society. The anthropologist
might appeal to concepts such as kinship, ritual, reciprocal friendships, all
components of culturally embedded value systems to explain phenomena such as
gift giving, barter, conditions of production, and so on – all within a context of decision-making,
choice and scarcity. But this is exactly what we have in modern market
economies: economic decisions are made within cultural contexts that set the
rules of the game. Consider how a non-human observer would describe and explain
the behaviour of elephants and humans. It is doubtful whether qualitatively
different models would be appealed to in these cases. There would be no need to
appeal to the models of neoclassical economics in this instance. No doubt, the
reason why the replacing of neoclassical economics with anthropology would not
be an attractive alternative is merely human narcissism and self-regarding
introspection.
The question concerning the relationship between
economics and anthropology has already been explored under the rubric of
economic anthropology. Consider, for example, the substantivism of Karl Polanyi
that viewed formal neoclassical theory as erroneously applicable to what are regarded
as non-market economies. Polanyi argued that it was an error to evaluate what
he called ‘archaic’ or ‘primitive’ economies with the same tools that were used
for the market economies of modern industrialized states. The economic life of
such societies was dominated by reciprocal gift-giving among kin and others for
the main purpose of maintaining status and individual dignity. Such societies
had no notion of the individualist utility maximising economic man of
neoclassical economics lore (Polanyi 1944).
Polanyi’s critique was directed against the idea that
the lives of humans in whatever cultural setting could be subjected to the
analytical tools of neoclassical economics. His countervailing thesis was that
in those societies
110
where economic life was
not dominated by the transactions of the market, the application of the
explanatory paradigm of neoclassical economics was not appropriate. Polanyi’s
argument in brief rests on the following assumption: ‘ instead of the economic
system being embedded in social relationships, these relationships were now
embedded in the economic system’ ( Polanyi
1968: 70). In
other words, market economics with its subordination of society to the
alternative twin dictates of starvation or profits has subverted traditional
social structures in which human social life was ultimately based on
noneconomic factors such as kinship and religion. In all these societies, according to Polanyi,
the guiding social ethos was reciprocity and redistribution. For Polanyi, the
theories of market economics should properly be restricted to post-Ricardian
industrialised society. In other words, a quantified version of utilitarianism
with the ascribed name of neoclassical economics was deemed sufficient to
account for the behaviour of humans within society. The pretensions here were
that this new discipline was sufficient to analyse human behaviour
scientifically. But based on the arguments in the discussion made above, this
approach has been shown to be problematic.
But if the descriptions and explanations of the economic
life of the Trobriand Islanders offered by the economic anthropology of a
Malinowski is sufficiently cognitively satisfying then why not the same for the
economic life of individuals within market economies? Polanyi’s argument would
be that the lives of humans within industrial society are directed strictly by
the dictates of the market mechanism. In this regard, economic behaviour is not
embedded in the prevailing culture, rather it is culture that has been suborned
by values of the market subculture. What are these values? They constitute an
assumed faith in business and property contracts, a strongly held belief in the
sanctity of private property, a firm belief that risk should be rewarded, that
humans are ultimately responsible for themselves principally without regard for
the general welfare of the social collective, that human empathy extends only
to the closest kin, and that humans are naturally hard-wired to seek out gain
in their impersonal transactions with each other. But all these beliefs and
their accompanying behaviours could be just as easily understood as those of
individuals whose anthropologies are those of non-market economies, by appeal
to the tools of economic anthropology.
Robinson Crusoe and the Human Challenge
Humans are not
driven by instinct as is the case of other mammals. Culture decides the rules
of conduct in practically all spheres of decision-making. So the kinds of
society that humans choose to establish reduce on the contingencies of culture
choice, pace the sociobiologists. It
is the case that
111
the economic behaviour of humans in groups
is determined by culture and its attendant ethics.
To illustrate the point
being made consider the case of the historical Robinson Crusoe – a metaphor for
colonialism and the expansion of capitalism – alone on his island. What kind of
economic system would he practice?
Crusoe would be self-governing and
owner of his own capital, that is, his own tools of production. He would be
productive as he saw fit and would share his production with himself only – as
hermits have been known to do.
But the question is this: what kind
of theories would some hypothetical researcher construct to account for the
behaviour and activities of Crusoe? Would this hypothetical researcher apply
the techniques of the neoclassical economist or appeal to the toolkit of the
anthropologist. Of course, the orthodox neoclassical economist would create
some sort of hypothetical Crusoe who would supposedly conform to the
behavioural rules prescribed by the theorist himself. It is obvious that more
would be learned about Crusoe’s decision-making by appeal to the techniques of
anthropology than to those of the neoclassical economist. The reason is that
the anthropologist as scientist would seek first to describe the behaviour of
Crusoe without appeal to some concept of rationality which might just be
culturally idiosyncratic to Crusoe himself. The anthropologist’s description
and explanatory analysis would
certainly fall within the context of what
the anthropology profession describes as cultural relativism. But the
neoclassical economist cannot afford to adopt this methodology given that the
neoclassical paradigm is firmly wedded to the positivist school of thought
which has traditionally argued for a ‘unity of science approach’ for all
objects of empirical inquiry. This would bring us again to the well-worn issue
concerning the appropriate methodology for the human or social sciences.
The goal of this paper all along has been to examine
whether theorists of neoclassical economics have been successful in
establishing a genuine science of economics given the efforts of its most
prominent methodologists. I have argued that neoclassical economics is
essentially a normative system founded on a generically neoclassical postulate
of rationality. Whether Crusoe decides to adopt the choice paths prescribed by
the neoclassical theorist can be best described by the anthropologist as an
economist. The same approach would be at work when the Crusoe story becomes
more interesting with the arrival of Friday. We venture here, of course, into
the area of welfare economics where the theorist openly admits that in this
instance value judgments hold sway.
So what are possibilities? Crusoe could capture
Friday and put him to work as a serf or a semi-free bondsman who must turn over
the major portion of the produce from the work imposed on him. Crusoe’s
argument
112
in support of the
economic structure set up would be that he ought to be rewarded for the capital
that he provided for Friday and the risks incurred by investing in Friday. That
is the neoclassical-neoliberal argument. But there are major risks involved for
Crusoe when Friday quickly realises that he is producing much more than he is
consuming. He is not free and he knows that Crusoe’s economic survival depends
on him. The Hegelian dialectic between master and bondsman has been activated.
Couple that necessary conflict with the capitalist crisis of overproduction
where Crusoe hoards the surpluses produced by Friday. Since Crusoe cannot
consume all the surpluses and has restricted Friday a bare minimum subsistence
quota, Friday must cease work and production. This is the dynamic of
neoclassical economics as capitalism.
Or Crusoe could choose to share his capital with Friday
with both individuals engaging in production – hunting, fishing, planting,
building, and so forth – and both sharing the output. But before embarking on
such, both would have worked out contractually the duties and obligations that
would determine how they would work together. Of course, what all this reduces
to are questions concerning issues of welfare economics in the context of the
questions raised by Pigou, Pareto and Arrow. Methodologically speaking, these are
the same questions that the neoclassical theorist must ask.The plain truth is
that all this would not be fully understood outside of the context of
anthropological analysis. Only anthropological analysis would inform that
neoclassical economic theory and its practice as capitalism should be
understood as the particular socio-anthropology of the West.
Conclusion
The purpose of
this paper is to demonstrate that despite its forays into revealed preference
theory and rationality, neoclassical economic theory remains inescapably
value-laden and as an instance of preference utilitarianism. The fact that
neoclassical theory is strongly held to represent an objective and scientific
economics would mean that its intent is ideological. The question then is whose
interests does neoclassical economics serve? The question is an important one
in that humans are the only living species that are equipped with the cognitive
skills to radically transform nature to satisfy survival needs. Yet we live in
a world in which the optimal human decision-making mechanism that could
maximize the vast multiplicities of human cognitive skills to attain the ends
of maximum human welfare in its myriad dimensions, has been usurped by
neoclassical economics whose creative destruction is embodied by the fabled
four horsemen of the Apocalypse. The point is that the whole human condition is
in dire need of rethinking and it should not be left to the purveyors of
neoclassical economics, an ideologically driven discipline that
113
has shaped the central ethos of
modern times. And what is that ethos but the culture of capitalism, a product
of the West. And although the most influential economist of the twentieth
century, John Maynard Keynes, saw fit to rescue capitalism from its self-destructive
activities that resulted in the economic crash of 1929, he still had little
faith in it as an economic system. Consider the following: ‘The outstanding
faults of the economic society in which we live are its failure to provide for
full employment and its arbitrary and inequitable distribution of wealth and
income’ (Keynes 1936:372). Those serious faults
of capitalism are still with us and causing
even more havoc.
The ploy of course is this: if neoclassical economics could
be proven to a be a science by way of RPT, then it would be argued that the
victims of capitalism and its instantiation as neoliberal economics would just
have to live with their victim status.
References
Afriat,
Sydney, 1976, The Combinatorial Theory of
Demand, London: InputOutput Publishing.
Ariely, Dan, 2008, Predictably
Irrational: The Hidden Forces that Shape our Decisions, New York: Free
Press.
Arrow,
Kenneth, 1951, Social Choice and Individual
Values, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Becker,
Gary, 1976, Economic Approaches to Human
Behaviour, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bentham, Jeremy, 1879, Introduction
to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Blaug, Mark,
1980, The Methodology of Economics, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Boland, Lawrence, 1981, ‘On
the Futility of Criticizing the Neoclassical Maximization
Hypothesis’,
American Economic Review 71,
1031-1036. Bridgman, Percy, 1927, The
Logic of Modern Physics, New York: Macmillan.
Camerer,
Colin, 1999, ‘Behavioral Economics: Reuniting Psychology’,Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the U.S.A., 19,
10575-10577.
Camerer,
Colin, G. Lowenstein, and D. Prelec, 2005, ‘Neuroeconomics: How Neuroscience
can Inform Economics’,Journal of Economic
Literature,43, 9-64.
Coats, A.W. 1996,
‘Utilitarianism, Oxford Idealism and Cambridge Economics’,in
Peter Groenewegen, ed., Economics and Ethics, London: Routledge.
Dalton,
George, ed., 1968, Primitive, Archaic and
Modern Economics, New York: Anchor Books.
Friedman, Milton, 1953, ‘The
Methodology of Positive Economics’, in Milton
Friedman, ed., Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
114
Green, Donald, and Shapiro,
Ian, 1994, Pathologies of Rational Choice
Theory, New Haven: Yale University Press. Groenewegen, Peter, ed., 1996, Economics and Ethics?London: Routledge.
Grune, Till, 2004, ‘The
Problems of Testing Preference Axioms with Revealed
Preference Theory’, Analyse
und Kritik, 382-397.
Hausman,
Daniel, and Mc Pherson, Michael, 1996, Economic
Analysis and Moral Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holland,
John. H., 1992 (a), Adaptation in Natural
and Artificial Systems, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Houthakker, Hendrik, 1983,
‘Consumption Theory’, inPaul Samuelson
and Modern
Economic Theory,E. C. Brown and R. M. Solow, eds, New York:
McGraw-Hill. Jevons, William, S., 1879, Theory
of Political Economy, London: McMillan.
Kahneman,
Daniel and Tversky, Amos, 1979, ‘Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under
Risk’, Econometrica, 47, 313-327.
Kahneman,
Daniel and Thaler, Richard, 2006, ‘Anomalies: Utility Maximization and
Experienced Utility’, Journal of Economic Perspectives.1,
221-234.
Keynes, J.M., 1936, The
General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money, London: Macmillan.
Kuhn,
Thomas, 1962, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions,Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Machlup, Fritz, 1966,
‘Professor Samuelson on Theory and Realism’, in Joseph
Stiglitz, ed.,The
Collected Scientific Works of P.A. Samuelson,Vol. I. Cambridge: M.I.T.
Press.
Mattei, Aurelio, 2000, ‘Full
Scale Real of Consumer Behaviour Using Experimental
Data’, Journal of
Economic Behaviour and Organization 43, 487-497.
Menger,
Carl, 1871, Principles of Economics, New
York: New York University Press, 1976 (English trans,).
Mises, Ludwig von, 1949, Human Action, New Haven: Yale University
Press. Polanyi, Karl, 2001, The Great
Transformation, Boston: Beacon Press.
Polanyi, Karl, 1968, ‘Our
Obsolete Market Economy’, in Primitive,
Archaic and
Modern Economies. George Dalton, ed., New York: Anchor Books.
Popper, Karl, 1968, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, New
York: Basic Books.
Popper, Karl, 1972, Objective Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Rosenberg,
Alexander, 1976, Microeconomics Laws, Pittsburgh:
The University of Pittsburgh Press.
Rosenberg, Alexander, 1992, Mathematical Politics or Science of
Diminishing Returns,Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rubenstein,
Ariel, 1998, Modeling Bounded
Rationality, Cambridge: MIT Press.
Samuelson, Paul, 1938 (a),
‘A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behaviour’,
Economica5, 61-71.
Samuelson, Paul, 1938 (b),
‘A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behaviour:
An Addendum’, Economica 5, 353-54.
Samuelson,
Paul, 1947, Foundations of Economic
Analysis, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
115
Samuelson, Paul, 1948,
‘Consumption Theory in Terms of Revealed Preference’,
Economica15, 243-53.
Samuelson, Paul, 1950, ‘The
Problem of Integrability in Utility Theory’,Economica
17, 355-85.
Samuelson, Paul, 1972,
‘Maximum Principles in Analytical Economics’,American
Economic Review, 62,
249-62.
Sanfey,
A.G., J.K. Rilling, J.A. Aronson, L.E. Nystrom, and J.D. Cohen, 2003, ‘The
Neural Basis of Economic Decision Making in the Ultimate Game’, Science,
300,1755-1758.
Sen, Amartya, 1987, On Ethics and
Economics, New York: Basil Blackwell.
Sent,
Esther-Mirjam, 2004, ‘The Legacy of Herbert Simon in Game Theory’,Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization. 53, 303-317.
Simon,
Herbert, 1955, ‘A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice’,Quarterly Journal of Economics.
Simon, Herbert, 1959,
‘Theories of Decision Making in Economics and Behavioral
Science’, American
Economic Review 49, 253-283.
Simon,
Herbert, 1982, Models of Bounded
Rationality, Vol. 2, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Simon, Herbert, 1986,
‘Rationality in Psychology and Economics’, The
Journal of
Business,59, 4, 209-224.
Sippel, Reinhard, 1997, ‘An
Experiment in the Pure Theory of Consumer’s
Behaviour’, The
Economic Journal 107, 1431-44.
Stiglitz,
Joseph, 1966, ed., The Collected
Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson,Vol. 1, Cambridge, MIT Press.
Thaler, Richard, 1992,The
Winner’s Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic
Life, New York: Free Press.
Varian, Hal, 2006, ‘Revealed
Preference’, in Michael Szenberg et al,eds,
Samuelsonian Economics and
the 21st Century (pre-publication draft).
Vanberg,
Viktor, 2004, ’The Rationality Postulate in Economics: Its Ambiguity,
Deficiency and its Evolutionary Alternative’, Journal of Economic
Methodology 11, 1, 1-29.
Varoufakis,
Yanis, 1996, ‘O Tempora, O Mores! Economics as the Ethos of Our Times’, in
Peter Groenewegen (ed.). London:
Routledge.
von
Neumann, John, and O. Morgenstern, 1944, Theory
of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Walras,
Leon, 1874,Elements of Pure Economics,William
Jaffe (trans.), Homewood, Ill.: Irwin, 1954 (1874).
White,
Michael, 1996, ‘Comment: No Matter of Regret: The Cambridge Critique(s) of
Jevons’s “Hedonics”’, in Economics and
Ethics, Peter Groenwegen (ed.), London: Routledge.
Wong, Stanley, 1973, ‘The
F-Twist and the Methodology of Paul Samuelson’,
American Economic Review 63, 312-25.
Wong, Stanley, 1978, The
Foundations of Paul Samuelson’s Revealed Preference
Theory, Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
No comments:
Post a Comment