
© Council for the Development of Social Science
Research in Africa, 2012
(ISSN 0850-3907)
On
Deligitimising Capitalism:
The Scourge
of Africa and the South
Samir Amin*
Abstract
Contrary to
orthodox belief the ongoing economic growth crisis in the West and the perpetual development crisis in Africa
derives from the problematic of capitalism. The situation in Africa of high
prices, inflation, massive unemployment and stunted growth is just taken as it
is and borne painfully but stocially. But all this is due to the structure of
capitalism which this paper seeks to explain. Marxian dynamic analysis, founded
on the law of value and its role in the accumulation of capital, is the method
of analysis employed. I explore results of such in terms of “unequal
development” in the context of the asymmetry of the “centreperiphery” dual
model. The discussion leads to an analysis of Walras's general equilibrium
model and paradoxical observation that capitalism never experiences a general
equilibrium. The “anti-law of value” theories of Walras, Sraffa, and Keynes are
analysed as they seek to transfer economic value from the product of labour to the gains of capital. The
critiques of Giovani Arrighi are also woven into the critical fabric. Contemporary liberal economists such as Joseph Stiglitz
are noted for their lack of full comprehension of the dynamics of the contemporary
form of capitalism which although seeking growth tends rather to stagnation in
the social context of human alienation. In the end it is globalised finance
capital that will prove to be the Archilles's heel of capitalism. It is at this
point that the nations of the South should be prepared to delink from the
capitalist as a precondition for genuine development. Necessarily this would
apply to the nations of Africa.
Résumé
Contrairement
à une croyance répandue, la crise de croissance actuelle en occident et la
persistante crise du développement en Afrique découlent de la problématique du
capitalisme. Le problème de la hausse des prix en Afrique, de l’inflation, du
chômage massif et de la faible croissance de l’économie sont juste perçus tels
qu’ils sont et supportes avec stoïcisme. Mais tout ceci est une conséquence de
la nature même

* Forum du
Tiers Monde, Dakar,
Senegal. Email:
samir.amin@wanadoo.com
16
du
capitalisme que cet article cherche à expliquer. L’analyse de la dynamique
marxiste, fondée sur la loi de la valeur et sur son rôle dans l’accumulation
primitive du capital, est la méthode d’analyse employée. J’observe ce genre de
résultats du point de vue du développement inégal dans le contexte de
l’asymétrie du modèle double de la périphérie du centre ? La discussion conduit
a une analyse du modèle de l’équilibre général de Walras et a l’observation
paradoxale (qui veut) que le
capitalisme
ne connaît jamais un équilibre général. Les théories de « antiloi de valeur »
de Walras, Sraffa et Keynes sur les théories des valeurs anti-loi sont
analysées sous l’angle de leur tendance à transférer la valeur économique du
produit du travail aux gains du capital. Les critiques de Giovani Arrighi
semblent, elles aussi, trempées dans le même genre très critique. Les
économistes libéraux contemporains comme Joseph Stiglitz sont connus pour leur
méconnaissance totale de la dynamique de la forme contemporaine du capitalisme
qui tout en visant la croissance s’occupe plutôt de la stagnation dans le
contexte social d’aliénation humaine. À la fin, c’est la capital de finance
globalisée qui s’avérera être le talon d’Achilles du capitalisme. C’est a ce
moment seulement que les
nations du Sud
devraient être préparées à se déconnecter du capitalisme comme une condition
nécessaire pour le vrai développement. Et cela devrait s’appliquer forcement
aux pays de l’Afrique.
Introduction
Since the twentieth century, Africa
has known only the capitalist system and its impact on African life. Violently
drawn into the capitalist system, firstly, as slaves, transported to the
Americas, and afterwards used as pawns in the colonialist system spearheaded by
the same countries enriched through Atlantic globalisation, African populations
became an integral part of the capitalist system. Right from the beginning and
into the twentieth century, nothing has really changed. Africa and Africans
continue to be exploited by the capitalist system for the well-being of the
capitalist nerve centre of the industrialised countries. The consequence is the
discontentment of Africa’s peoples on all fronts.
The problem is that today’s African does not know any
other economic and cultural system than capitalism. And even African
lecturers-cumresearchers and their students, in general, seldom wonder if
alternatives exist. The reason for this is that education in post-colonial
universities only takes into account the rules and mechanics of the
neoclassical economic system. The severe effects of neoliberal economic
initiatives such as Structural Adjustment Programmes, open market diktats,
NEPAD, etc., are all meant to continue to extract ‘imperialist rent’ from
Africa’s suffering populations and others from the South. Low wages, low
commodity prices, high import prices for the same processed commodities,
massive unemployment coupled
17
with significant
underemployment, punishing exchange rates, resource wars, the coddling of the
firmly entrenched corrupt, comprador classes of Africa and the South, the
flight of capital – physical, monetary, and human – etc., are all instances of
the debilitating extraction of ‘imperialist rent’ from Africa. All this is
founded on my original theses of the ‘centre-periphery’ paradigm always
characterised by ‘unequal exchange’. So, Que
faire ? The long-term goal is a socialist world of ‘equal exchange’ and the
abolition of ‘imperialist rent’. In the short term, Africa’s labouring classes
and its intellectuals should militate to put an end to the ongoing extraction
of ‘imperialist rent’ from Africa by way of debilitating ‘unequal exchange’.
This can be done through worker organization and cooperation, and concerted
democratic processes which would hold accountable the decisions made by those
voted into power. The question they must be constantly made to answer is: ‘Are
you on the side of imperialism or on the side of the people?’ There are grounds
for optimism given the ongoing
crisis of capital in the Eurozone and
the United States.
This is why my purpose in this article is to analyse and
explain the capitalist economic system which causes so much discontentment and
anxiety in contemporary Africa. In reality, alternatives exist, but it is first
necessary to understand this system and the misfortunes it is causing today. To
fight the disease it is necessary to understand its aetiology. The goal is to
render the ideology and practice of capitalism illegitimate for the development
of Africa.
I offer, in this article, to develop salient points to
show the objective reasons which clearly reveal that capitalism, considered in its
entirety as mode of management of the economy and of our social life, is an
obsolete system. Alas! The widely-held view that lends legitimacy to this
system because it guarantees economic efficiency born from competition on which
it is founded, as well as political democracy, is groundless. In fact, it can,
convincingly, be shown that capitalism feeds an irrational and extremely
dangerous vision on three levels from a social and human point of view. The
conventional analytical paradigm used by most economists in the world is that
of neoclassical economics. With the political and economic transformations that
took place in the Soviet Union and China, a triumphal neoclassical economics
with its practice as neoliberalism on the world scale was being touted as the
optimal economic system available. The pundits were wrong as the severe ongoing
crisis of capitalism proves. The pundits of neoclassical economics were
incapable of predicting and explaining the severe economic recession of 2007.
On the contrary, Marxist economic analysis is much better equipped, both in
terms of depth and width, to understand, explain and predict the present
situation. The same applies to the unending economic crisis in Africa.
Neoclassical economics and its practice as neoliberalism can neither explain
nor solve the economic problems of
18
Africa. The Marxist model offers a
better understanding of how capitalism operates in Africa as it seeks to
extract imperialist rent from its victims according to its voracious need for
continuing accumulation. It is on this basis that nations of the South, and
Africa in particular, must reject the enterprise of capitalism if they are
going to develop. This is the reason why capitalism must be delegitimised as
the optimal model for African development. This essay seeks to explain why this
is so. Capitalism operates on what I note as three levels. They are as follows.
•
First
Level: the reproduction of the extensive accumulation of capital (capital
development) in capitalism demands
monopolies which have characterised this system since the end of the
nineteenth century through the growth of dependent, useless, and destructive
activities, with the sole objective of absorbing a growing surplus which cannot
be invested to increase and sustain productive and useful activities.
•
Second
Level: the reproduction of accumulation, on a global scale, produces,
reproduces and deepens the gap worldwide and allows the hold of an imperialist
revenue in uninterrupted growth to the detriment of the people and nations of the
periphery of this globalised system, which is, in itself, an increasing
obstacle to the building of the multi-pole world that guarantees equal respect
of the rights of nations.
•
Third
Level: products alienation, the reification of social relations as well as
the commercialisation of economic management, all inseparable from capitalism
which ruins possibilities needed to induce progress for the liberation of human
beings and societies.
No alternative capitalism is possible as Remy
Herrera strongly continues to point out. The internationalist socialist
perspective is the only realistic alternative to the barbarism perpetuated
through the pursuit of the capitalist action called ‘development’ (or more
simply the endless GDP growth based on capital development).
Part I: The Expansion of Economic Surplus
In my book The Law of Value and Historical Materialism (1977, a new edition is
expected soon in French and English), I proposed to identify the
characteristics and the conditions for extensive accumulation, formulated for a
system that is reduced to its two departments which are: I - production of
assets, and II - production of consumer goods, in a simple model.
From this simple model, we draw two
conclusions:
(i) That
extensive accumulation requires real wage growth defined by a combination of
productivity growth rates in Departments I and II;
19
(ii) The
rate of economic growth (the sum of wages and capital gains, which in turn
controls employment, is determined by the rate of accumulation, which is also
controlled by the rate of capital gain (the percentage of capital gain in
comparison to net proceeds: salaries + capital gain) and the rates of progress
of social labour productivity.
These two findings are crucial in
understanding that capitalism truly exists.
The natural tendency of capital is not to guarantee the growth
of real wage as required, but to keep it as low as social conditions permit.
This fundamental and enduring contradiction reflects the history of capitalist
development in its true dimensions. It helps amongst others:
(i)
to understand why the glorious phase of this
development was remarkably short, and corresponds to the beginning of
capitalism from the Industrial Revolution to the nineteenth century. During
this early period, extensive accumulation was made possible, despite the
stagnation (and even regression) of wages, by its expansion at the expense of
segments of the non-capitalist productive system, because it disintegrated
(ruined craftsmen and poor peasants fuelled the expansion of paid labour) and
integrated into its system (demand was fuelled by the expansion of commercial
agriculture and that of new middle classes). The huge investments in
infrastructure (railways, among others) that the new spatial planning imposed
complete the picture of this established and completed capitalism.
(ii) Marx
had fully understood that capitalism was not the end of the story, but rather a
brief interlude during which conditions would be, finally, in place to enable
its being rapidly overtaken.
(iii) To
understand why, after this rapid implementation, capitalism entered its long
crisis with an economic face seen through the emerging spectrum of stagnation
(from 1873) and the political face as seen through its questioning by the
Commune de Paris (1871). Capital responded to this structural crisis through
monopolisation, globalisation and financialisation. The accumulation method was
transformed, and henceforth based on the continued expansion of Department III
– on absorption of growing surplus, as Baran, Sweezy and Magdoff demonstrated.
I also analysed in this way the second long crisis of capitalism that began in
the 1970s, and came into a new phase of its evolution with the 2008 financial
disintegration. Here, I refer the reader to my analysis of these two long
crises of matured (in real fact, obsolete) capitalism.
20
It is not hard to see why, in the
absence of real wage growth at a definable rate (by the growth rate of social
labour productivity), capital accumulation is possible only if there is a
department III for the absorption of surplus, which is defined as the excess of
capital gain over its fraction to be invested in expanding and deepening the
productive system (investments in Departments I and II). We can even measure
the growth rate of the volume of department III, which is based on the
difference between the growth of net proceeds and real wage growth.
For example, let us assume the growth rate of social
labour productivity is in the order of 4.5 per cent per annum, ensuring a
doubling of net proceeds over a period of fifteen years, which corresponds to
the average life of equipment. To simplify this reasoning, it can be assumed
that the organic compositions and growth rates of labour productivity for
Departments I and II are stable. The introduction of different assumptions
would require the use of algebraic representation of this example, which is
easy to write but may be difficult to read for non-mathematicians. The
consideration of this complication would not affect the conclusions illustrated
by the example, since real wage growth is lower than net proceeds.
Let us imagine that real wage growth is, in the long
term, of about 3.5 per cent per annum, thereby ensuring its increase to 70 per
cent over 15 years.
This leads to changes in key variables of the example
according to the illustration that follows (figures rounded up).
|
Net Income
|
Wages
|
Profits
|
Surplus
|
Year 1
|
100
|
50
|
50
|
0
|
Year 15
|
200
|
70
|
70
|
60
|
Year 30
|
400
|
100
|
100
|
200
|
Year 45
|
800
|
140
|
140
|
520
|
After half a century of continuous
and regular evolution of the system, surplus, (which defines the volume of
Department III in relation to net income, itself sum of wages, reinvested
profits and surplus), absorbs two-thirds of net proceeds (roughly the GDP).
This is roughly what actually happened during the
twentieth century for the developed centres of global capitalism (the triad:
United States, Europe, and Japan).
Keynes had keenly observed that mature capitalism was
struck by a latent tendency to unyielding stagnation. But he had not explained
it, as this would have required him to seriously consider the substitution of
monopoly capitalism with the classical model of competition. His explanation
remains, therefore,
21
tautological: stagnation is
the result of the fall – unexplained – of the marginal
efficiency of capital (below the
liquidity preference).
Initially, that is to say until the 1914 war, surplus was
reduced almost to government spending financed by taxes, of about 10 to 15 per
cent of GDP at most. These were the expenses of sovereignty (state, police and
army), expenses associated with the public management of certain social
services (education and health) and the development of certain infrastructure
(bridges and roads, ports, railways).
Analysis of the components corresponding to the concept
of surplus reveals the diversity of status governing their management.
Marx’s Departments I and II correspond – approximately
– to the sectors defined respectively in national accounts as primary (agricultural production and
mining), secondary (processing
industries), and a fraction of activities called tertiary that it is not always easy to spot in the statistics
(which were not designed for this purpose), even though the definition of their
status does not cause confusion.
•
Must be selected as participating – indirectly –
to the production of
Departments I and II: transport equipment,
raw materials and final products, trade in these products, management costs of
financial institutions at their service.
• Are
not to be taken into account as components of direct and indirect production of
Departments I and II, and should be considered as part of the surplus:
government spending, social transfers (education, health, social security,
pensions and retirements), the services corresponding to selling costs
(advertising) services to individuals covered by the spending of income
(accommodation included).
The private or public nature of the management
of the services in question, classified in national accounts under the tertiary
sector (with the possible distinction among them from a new sector called
quaternary), does not define, in itself, the association to Department III
(surplus).
Still, today the volume of the tertiary sector is already
in itself far more than primary and secondary activities in the developed
countries of the centre (but also in many countries of the periphery, but this
issue – different – is not ours here). Also the amount of taxes and mandatory
contributions, alone, reaches – or exceeds – 40 per cent of these countries’
GDP. The speech by some straight ideological fundamentalists calling for the
reduction of these taxes is purely demagogic: capitalism cannot function
otherwise. In fact any reduction in taxes paid by the rich must necessarily be
offset by a higher taxation of the poor!
22
One can thus estimate without fear of committing a
major error that the surplus (Department III) constitutes half of the GDP or,
in other words, it passed from 10 per cent in the nineteenth century to 50 per
cent in the first decade of this century. And ifat the time of Marx, therefore,
an analysis of the accumulation reduced to the consideration of departments I
and II made sense, it is no longer the case. The enrichment brought to Marxist
thought by Baran, Sweezy and Magdoff by their consideration of Department III (and
the concept of ‘surplus’ which is associated with it, defined as we
mentioned) is, therefore, crucial. I
regret that most analysts of contemporary Marxism are still in doubt!
Once again, everything in this surplus is not to be
condemned as being parasitic and useless. Far from it! On the contrary, the
growth of a good portion of the expenditure associated with this Department III
deserves to be supported; and, in a much later stage of development of human
civilisation, it would have to still take on more importance, like education,
health, social security and retirement policy, or even other services
associated with deploying forms of socialisation through democracy to replace
the socialisation of the market (public transport, housing and others). On the
other hand, certain components of Department III – such as the costs of sale in
exponential growth during the twentieth century, identified as such, very
early, by some economists less or badly considered by the profession (like Joan
Robinson) – are obviously of parasitic nature. One can also treat, similarly,
certain public (armament) or private (private police, armed forces lawyers,
etc) expenditure.
A large portion of Department III certainly had profitable advantages to workers and
supplemented their direct wages (social security, pensions). Nevertheless,
these hard-won advantages by the working class were questioned during the last
three decades; some seriously reduced, and others transferred from a
social-solidarity-based public management to an alleged individual rights-based
private management. This management style, dominant in the United States, and
in progression in Europe, opens up additional possibilities for surplus
investments, in turn, very well remunerated!
But it remains that in capitalism, all of these uses
of the GDP – useful or not – fulfil the same function: to allow continued
accumulation despite insufficient growth in labour incomes. In addition, the
permanent battle on the choice of management – by the replacement of private
management with the public management of many components of Department III –
provides capital with additional opportunities for profit-making (and to,
consequently, increase the surplus volume!). In the United States, private
medicine believes that if the patient must be treated, he must surely enrich
(private clinics, laboratories, pharmaceutical companies and health insurance
companies)!
23
My analysis on Department III of surplus absorption
falls within the context of the pioneering works of Baran and Sweezy. The
ultimate conclusion is that an important proposal of activities managed within
this context is, indeed, parasitic and inflates the GDP, depriving it of much
of its significance as an indicator of the real degree of richness of the
society.
In counterpoint, it is fashionable today to consider the
rapid growth of this Department as an indicator of the transformation of
capitalism, from the industrial age to the knowledge economy. Thus, the endless
pursuit of capital appreciation finds its legitimacy. The expression ‘cognitive
capitalism’ is, in itself, an oxymoron. Tomorrow’s economy, of socialism, will,
well, be cognitive; capitalism cannot be. Imagine that the development of the
productive forces, by itself, sets up – in capitalism – tomorrow’s economy, as
inspired by the writings of Negri and his followers, is only seemingly correct.
For capital appreciation, necessarily based on the submission of work,
annihilates the progressive and transformer aspect of this development. This
annihilation is at the heart of the definition of Department III, designed to
absorb the inseparable surplus associated with monopoly capitalism.
Imperialist Rent
Imperialist rent is the result of
unequal development of truly existing globalised capitalism, pertinently of the
polarisation generated by the globalised expansion of capital domination and
the differential in prices of the work force (with equal productivity) which is
associated to it. This polarisation, unceasingly produced, reproduced and
deepened from one phase of globalised expansion of capital to the other,
destroys the possibility for peripheral countries of this globalised system to
catch up with the dominant centres, i.e., to resemble, the opulent capitalist
societies. It is, thus, for the people and the nations of the periphery (Asia,
Africa and Latin America, which constitute 80 per cent of the human population)
the major reason which should completely nullify any legitimacy of capitalism.
However, this reality does not, necessarily, exist in
the minds of the people and nations concerned. More so, as the concerned
societies are class societies where the dominant classes – in modern times –
were largely created (or recreated) by the global expansion of capitalism.
Thus, large numbers of these dominant classes are stakeholders in the system
which ensures their privileged position in their respective societies on the
economic and political fronts. On their side, the classes dominated and
exploited, simultaneously – by dominating capital on a global scale and by the
local classes/driving forces of this domination – are not, more than others,
spontaneously conscious of the real reasons of their misery.
24
Discovering, through scientific analysis of veritable
globalised capitalism, the mechanisms (economic) which generate polarisation
and consequent imperialist rent is an imperative requirement in critical
reflection
I have devoted much of my important and personal
work for over fifty years to this task. This is why I will neither even try,
here, to summarize the stages, nor the theoretical reasoning for this purpose,
nor the confrontations with empirical realities essential for checking the
validity of this work. I will return only to my recent work (underway for
publication in French and English), precisely on the analysis of what I called
the metamorphosis of the law of value to the ‘law of globalized value’ (the title
of the book!).
Reading Marx
I was an early Marx reader. This work
certainly filled me with intellectual pleasure and the convincing power of
Marx’s thoughts. But, simultaneously, it left me hungering for more. For I was
asking myself a key question, about ‘underdevelopment’, (a new term often used
when I started this reading in the 1950s), of the societies of Asia and
contemporary Africa, for which I did not find an answer in Marx. The texts read
later when they were published in French for the first time in 1960 (Grundrisse) left me with the same
hunger.
Without giving up on Marx and judging him as
outdated, I concluded that his work had remained unfinished. Marx had not
completed his work as he had planned through the integration, on the one hand,
in his analysis of the global dimension of capitalism and, on the other hand,
the systematic evocation of politics and of economy (capitalist and before) –
beyond what the overly brilliant indications that his treatment of the French
revolutions (from the Great Revolution of 1871 through 1848) can provide on the
subject.
The question of (unequal) development which is the
reality of globalised capitalism thus brought me, as a student, to focus on the
first of these dimensions. My doctorate thesis (Accumulation on a Global Scale, 1957) testifies to this. It was,
for me, a beginning, a first step in the work I continued during the following
fifty years. I will not recall the successive moments of the development. I
believe it is only useful to highlight the overall formulation of the question
of unequal development which I proposed in 1973 in the book with the same
title, and in two other works written at the same time: The Law of Value and Historical Materialism (1977) and Unequal Exchange (1973).
To arrive at this formulation, I had chosen to deepen
my reflexion in these two directions, while being directly inspired by the
superb lesson that Marx himself had given us on the matter. Initially, I read,
attentively, the great works on conventional economics produced after Marx, in
answer to Marx, as Marx had taught us to, through his criticism of classical
economy
25
and its previous orthodox idea. This
implied the complete reading of Bohm Bawerk, Walras, Sraffa and other producers
of the foundation of the new empiricist or subjectivist economy including
Keynes’ formulations. This
critical reading is already proposed in the
first version ofAccumulation (1957),
and undertaken again in Unequal
Development (1973). ‘Reading Marx’ today – i.e. after Marx – imposes this
critical reading which convinced me of the orthodox, ideological character in
the functional sense of the term, of the new bourgeois economy, post and
anti-Marxist.
Marx, in his time, went beyond the theoretical criticism
of his precursors. He had, equally, provided an ordered presentation of
substantial empirical data. I thus thought that, similarly, post-Marx criticism
of bourgeois economy would be insufficient. And that it was necessary to, also,
complete this criticism through the ordered presentation of facts illustrating
the reality of the globalised development of capitalism. I proposed the first
blend of this mass of empirical data in Accumulation;
and then updated it for the publications of the 1970s. I continued this work,
while monitoring the then on-going developments – that of the first ‘awakening
of the South’ that the period of Bandung (1955-1980) represented. Attentive
readers of my writings – mainly British and Asian – noticed these empirical
studies.
The continuation comprises two sections: the so-called
development economy on the one hand, and the depth of markets analysis (and the
role of anticipations) on the other hand.
The first of these sections seemed, generally, rather
poor, restricted to the decreed vision of the fundamental stages of growth. I
had formulated the radical criticism of this mechanist and orthodox vision
three years before Rostov expressed it in his 1960 work. And since then, never
has the ‘development economy’ proposed by major institutions that intervene in favour
of this economy (the World Bank, cooperation programmes, universities) gone
beyond these idiocies.
The second section seemed to continue the neoclassical
vision while carrying it to a logical end: construction of an imaginary economy
– that of generalised markets – unrelated to truly existing capitalism. The
centrality of the empty and unreal concept of anticipation, that is needed for
this construction, completes this vision. Economic theory became pedagogic, leading
to the discussion of something like the ‘sex of angels’, while thinking like
the predecessors of the Middle Ages, that the answer to this question is the
only means through which one can understand the world. Simultaneously, this
self-proclaimed empirical, vision undertakes to integrate, into its proposed theses,
a growing mass of – disordered – empirical data. The mathematical method that
this action imposes is certainly not to be rejected. But the continued
26
sophistication of its methods does
not abolish the absurd – unrealistic – character of the questions of its users:
the anticipations (the sex of angels?).
Neither the criticism that I made on the orthodox
theory and its paraempirical applications, nor the counter proposals developed
and proposed as counterpoint to integrating the ordered data into a theory of
truly existing globalised capitalism, seemed sufficient to me, in understanding
all the reality of unequal development. The articulation of the political,
ideological, and cultural dimensions and that which relates to economic
management of the society is, indeed, the backdrop for an imperative historic
materialist read. And here, my reading Marx had already convinced me, as
reiterated, that his first proposals dare one to advance. What I tried to do by
proposing, on the one hand, a general concept of tributary mode of production,
base of the large family of organisations of societies of advanced
anti-capitalists classes: I opposed the articulation dominating power/dominated
economy to that, inversely particular to capitalism, and I drew some important
conclusions from them on the forms of alienation specific to old historical
societies and to modern capitalist society.
I also sought, in the varied forms, the existence of
real contradictions which operate therein, accelerating or delaying capitalist
development. I thus tried to integrate the questions on historical materialism
and on economic dimension, as the reader of Unequal
Development and The Law of Value and
Historical Materialism (1977) will notice.
My work was never that of a ‘marxologist’. I have
repeated unceasingly that for me ‘to be Marxist’ was to start from Marx and not
to stop with him, or with his major successors (Lenin and Mao), exponents of
historical Marxism. The central axis of my conclusions is defined by the
formulation of a ‘law of globalized value’, coherent with the bases of the law
of value which is particular to capitalism as discovered by Marx on the one
hand, and to realities of unequal globalised development on the other hand.
What I will dare to describe as my humble
contributions to the enrichment of the analysis of Marx are varied, in
particular given their importance as regards the design of nature and the range
of major contradictions and conflicts associated to them in contemporary
capitalism. I did not hesitate in contributing to complete the proposals of
Marx, even to correct them. I thus announce here my developments on the role of
credit in Accumulation (in answer to
the question of surplus by Rosa Luxemburg); my key analyses of the growth of
Department III on the absorption of profit (inspired by the pioneering works of
Baran, Sweezy and Magdoff); my criticisms of the theories of Marx on the
determinations of interest rate and of land revenue and my alternative
propositions in these areas – my criticisms of conventional economics.
27
My major contribution is on the transition from the law of
value to the law of globalised value, based on a hierarchy – itself globalised
– of prices of labour force around its value. With the management practices of
access to natural resources, this globalisation of value is the basis of the
imperialist rent. I claim that this globalisation of value controls the
elaboration of the major contradictions of truly existing
capitalism/imperialism and conflicts associated with them, in such a way that
social classes and nations are caught up in their fights and conflicts, in all
the complexity of their specific and concrete articulations. I claim that
twentieth and twenty-first centuries’ reads cannot be other than that of
emergence – or awakening – of the peoples and nations of the peripheries from
the globalised capitalist/imperialist system.
The Fundamental Nature of the Law of Value
The analysis of goods, and of the form of
value which defines it, is inevitable for whoever intends to understand what
capitalism really is. The scientific/ political economy of this system cannot
choose to overlook the law of value. Orthodox bourgeois economics in all its
successive formulations, selfproclaimed neoclassical (the misleading
appellation by which it lays claims to ‘science’) never managed – and will
never manage – to establish a criterion of ‘rationality’ of the system of
observed prices unrelated to the rate of
labour exploitation (the rate of
profit). I will come back to this crucial criticism of orthodox (non-Marxist,
even anti-Marxist) economics.
On the other hand, I then analysed the metamorphoses of
value, from its transformation into production price, then into market price,
and finally into the law of globalised value.
From
Production Prices to Market Prices
If competition of fragmented capital
suffices to transform values into production prices, it is nevertheless
necessary to consider a third component of operative realities which transform
production prices into market prices.
The first element here is the existence of oligopolies, which
negate the liberal assumption of competition. These oligopolies, which define
the truly existing capitalism – as Marx and Braudel after him have done – are
able to tax all profits from monopoly rents that guarantee profit rates above
those registered by dominated capital segments. Baran and Sweezy had, from
1966, started this analysis of monopoly capitalism. Extending this analysis, I
advanced the thesis that the advanced degree of capital centralisation that now
characterises contemporary capitalism deserved to underline for the first time
the generalised, globalised and financialised oligopoly system, foundations for
the configuration of collective economic power of the triad (US, Europe and
Japan). A Marxist thesis that few dare propose, for fear of being – wrongly –
equated to Kautsky and his thesis of super-imperialism.
28
The second intervention element in the determination
of market prices challenges the theoretical analysis of the functions of
monetary standard. Marx proposes here major and interesting developments for
the production of commodity/standard (gold) and the creation / destruction of
currency by credit. I also proposed some theories on this issue under new
conditions of widespread abandonment of the metallic standard (Unequal Development). The fact is that
human societies – because of their alienation (i.e., commodity alienation
inherent in capitalism) – still need a fetish. Hence, for our modern world,
gold remains the ultimate resort, as
seen in moments of crisis of accumulation – such as ours, for example.
A third component of disparate elements that either
define the general situation (easy growth periods and sharpening periods of
capitals competition) or specific situations (new products versus products with
exhausted expansion potential), intervene in turn in the determination of
observed prices in the markets.
Is an
Empiricist Approach to Accumulation Possible?
The strictly empiricist philosophical
spirit of the Anglo-Saxon world, carried over into all contemporary
conventional economics, prefers to retain only observed facts (prices such as
they are), directly deducing laws from it enabling understanding of the
mechanisms of reproduction of the system and its expansion. For the
professional economist, and hardcore empiricist, the detour through value is
burdening and useless.
One could be contented to respond that to understand
capitalism, it is not enough to understand its economic laws, but also to
understand the relations between these laws and the general conditions of its
social reproduction, that is to say the functioning of its ideological
authority in its relationships with its base. The law of value occupies a key
position that favours one to grasp this reality in the overall richness of its
entirety. Those who operate the reduction we condemn always end up imagining
socialism only as ‘capitalism without capitalists’.
But this argument, as fundamental as it is, is not
the only one. In fact, the empiricist treatment of the question which
economises this ‘burdening and useless detour through value’ – replacing it
with the direct understanding of the expressed reality in market price traps
one in a dead end. What will happen if, indeed, we placed our analysis, undertaken
within a context strictly inspired by Capital,
with an analysis inspired by price, using the Sraffa type of model?
The difference between the two methods lies in two
areas to be carefully separated: a) the replacement of price with values; and
b) the adoption of a production system of branches in place of the two
departments specialised in the production of capital goods and consumer goods.
The major drawback
29
of price analysis compared to value
analysis does not result from the open nature of the Sraffa model (i.e., that
the balance in the dynamics of supply and demand of each product, capital goods
and consumer goods, is not formalised as an internal condition of the model,
but simply and supposedly driven externally), as opposed to the closed
character (knotted) of Marx’s model (where the balance question is formalised
in the same model). This drawback is from the replacement of prices, which
depend on distribution, with values that do not depend on distribution. Thus,
the concept of progression of labour productivity (as a measure of development
of productive forces), which is perfectly objective with Marx (it does not
depend on profit rate), is no longer the case with Sraffa or with any model
expressed in price. Certainly, a system defined in prices is perfectly
determined - in the sense that relative prices and profit rates are – the
moment the real wage rate is given. But then there arises the question of a
standard where Sraffa, in Ricardian tradition, defines the condition for
validity as follows: it is a standard that would leave the net proceed
unchanged while distribution (wages and profits) changes autonomously.
Sraffa does not analyze the system like Marx. He eliminates
labour from the productive process to consider wages, not as the value of
labour, but as a category of distribution. Sraffa also proposes, and as we
know, to choose as standard the price of net proceeds. With this standard,
profit rate and wages are in a linear relationship independent of price, and
designated by a straight line, while any other given standard shows a
relationship between wages and profit rate that is neither linear nor monotonic.
Is the standard proposed by Sraffa better than another? No:
(i) because this standard involves the Sraffan treatment of wage; if it (wage)
is integrated into the production process as variable capital, standard varies
when wage varies: it is no longer independent of prices, (ii) because, even in
Sraffan formulation, the net proceed is changing over time (as a result of
growth), the standard is, thus, not independent of price, it is elastic. This
is no longer a standard. If we then reinstate wages in the productive process,
as it must be done, no matter the standard, we can always express profit rate
based on salary. But the relationship is neither linear, nor even necessarily
monotonically decreasing.
It does not do justice
to Marx to reduce his proposal – to choose value as the standard for price – to
demonstrate that this standard works, i.e., to say that transformation is
possible. The debate on transformation is a false case against Marx that comes
from a positivist / empiricist Capital, totally foreign to Marx’s method. I
will not return to this issue which I have fully explored in my major writings.
I simply repeat that, by the transformation of
30
value into price, the profit rate
that the system expression of value allows to calculate differs from the profit
rate observable in any system directly formulated in price, and does not reveal
a mistake from Marx, but is instead a key discovery to understanding the nature
of capitalism. Science requires that research goes beyond appearances to
discover what is hidden behind. If both rates were similar, aligning underlying
reality and visible appearance, there would be no need for scientific logic to
understand the world; we would only need to look at it! Of course, economists
whose scientific philosophy makes do with empiricist positivism cannot
understand the scope of discovery (and not the blunder) of Marx. This discovery
is the key that gives alienation in capitalism its entire dimension. I will
return to this question.
In fact, Marx was looking for a yardstick for
measuring the progress of productive forces. This yardstick is value. Indeed,
the amount of social necessary labour is the only wealth of society in the long
run. And value is independent of distribution.
One can show the relationship between wages and
profit rate in an illustration where salary is plotted as the ordinate (so it
goes from zero to the highest maximum possible point when it absorbs the entire
net income) and the profit rate on the abscissa (the profit rate is maximal
when the wage is zero).
In this illustration, we must interpret system
transformations from one phase to another by reading them on the y-axis. The
system that maximises the net income minimises the necessary social labour-time
to produce a sum of values of a given usage. It, thus, corresponds to more
efficient, more developed productive forces. The Sraffa yardstick compares the
systems along the x-axis. For zero wage, profit absorbs the entire proceeds.
The system that maximises profit rate will be considered as superior. This is
not the same thing.
Along the ordinate axis, the comparison of systems
simultaneously considers all coefficients corresponding to goods input and the
coefficients defining direct labour inputs. On the contrary, to compare
productive systems along the x-axis, for which wage is zero, is to consider
only the first coefficients (production of goods by goods and not by goods and
direct work) and neglecting the coefficients of direct labour inputs. The value
yardstick is higher because it, solely, considers production as a result of all
the technical coefficients that describe it.
There is therefore no way of ignoring the theory of
value. It allows us to link all the economic variables (price and income) to a
common denominator – value, that is to say, the amount of necessary social
labour – independent
of distribution rules (operating,
competition etc). And this is for characterising a given phase (synchronic
static analysis) as well as for measuring change
31
from one phase to another (diachronic dynamic
analysis) of the progress of productive forces.
In the Saffran system, by replacing wages with their
equivalent (goods consumed by employees), work disappears from production
equations ; goods are no more produced than with the help of goods without work
(which remains fundamental); surplus is entirely due to capital, which becomes
the sole factor of production!
We have here reached the highest stage of alienation: goods
(workers’ subsistence) create goods (a larger quantity of goods) without work.
We can compare this supreme alienation to the financier, who while making money
with money, qualifies money as being solely productive. Or again, we can remove
material inputs by replacing them with their equivalent in time worked. We
would thus have a system with only a single factor, labour, but timed, and we
fall back into the productive-time factor of Bohm Bawerk.
The empiricist approach – and that of Sraffa expresses
the most rigorous attempt – not permitting to establish a rationality of price
system independent of the rate of labour exploitation. It does not allow it in
its general model. And therefore it does not give the differential rates of
labour exploitation, in the truly existing global capitalism, the central
importance that it has. It is this difference – foreign to Sraffa’s method –
which shows the imperialist rent, the scope of which only the transformation of
the law of value into the law of globalised value allows to capture.
The Sraffa structure does not lend itself to analysis of
conditions from equilibrium to dynamic, since it does not address the
supply/demand balance of each product type (equipment, consumption) as in
Marx’s structure. This
is an empirical and poor model that
allows, at the most, to describe an observed trend, but not to draw evolution
laws from it.
All post-Marxian economics worked – to
abandon Marx – by locating the
origin of progress outside social work. This
economics invented for this purpose specific productivities of factors of
production, or reduced them to commodity (Sraffa: goods produce goods), or that
of money (money produces silver), or that of time (time is money, the
depreciation of the future in Bohm-Bawerk), or – today – that of science
(‘cognitive capitalism’, with precursor the marginal efficiency of capital as
Keynes understood it). Here, it is just forms of fundamental alienation,
particular to conventional bourgeois social thought.
Marx completed his assessment of capitalist reality with
assessment, whether it concerned those produced by great classics, founders of
modern thought in the field of new political economy (Smith, Ricardo, et al),
or those of orthodox economics, already present at the time (Bastiat).
Criticism of post-Marxian economists is no less necessary. It was made by some
Marxists out of the straitjacket of exegesis, sadly out of fashion. I note my
32
contributions to the assessment of
the best conventional economy that extends the classics (Walras, Keynes,
Sraffa, et al), to criticism of new forms of conventional economics
(‘witchcraft in modern times’, I wrote), that the reader might find in Unequal Development and Critique de l’air du temps (Harmattan
1997).
Is the Law
of Value Valid?
The identification of value as the
core of the critical analysis of capitalism economy, and then of its masked
presence by operations of its transformation into observed prices is not
without its problems. Developments by Marx on these issues demands of Marxists
not to be limited to the analysis of their texts but to dare to go further. In
particular, in terms of treatment of (i) concrete works with diverse
qualifications and their reduction to the concept of abstract labour, (ii) the
time required for the production, circulation and production of profit and from
the relationship between living labour /transferred dead labour, (iii) the
identification of usage values, (iv) the processing of natural resources,
whether they are subject to private ownership or not, (v) of appropriate
definition, specific to capitalism, social work and analysis of its
relationship to other forms of labour, (vi) the highlighted forms of absorption
of profit by Department III.
The evolution of capitalism since Marx’s time and the
huge changes it has produced challenges Marxist analysis. A perspective that
seeks to remain critical, and deepen this radical criticism of capitalism,
requires going beyond Marx’s answers to the challenges involved in these
issues. Some Marxists, including myself, are engaged in this endeavour. My
interventions in these debates such as the proposals I made in response to
challenges were summarily reproduced in From
Capitalism to Civilization (Tulika Books, 2010:84 - 95).
The time is not conducive for the pursuit of these
enrichment projects of Marxism, conceived limitlessly in its fundamental
criticism of the reality of the capitalist world. Instead of enriching Marxist
thought, we prefer to bury it and pretend to start over at zero. One is then
often prisoner – whether one realizes it or not – to orthodox thought, by
nature non-critical. The radical
criticism of the concept
of progress reduced to GDP growth that I proposed (From Capitalism to Civilization, Chapter 3, from page 98 onwards)
and – in counterpoint – the thesis I have adopted, equating progress to
emancipation
(Eurocentrism,
Modernity, Religion and Democracy, introductory chapter,
Pambazuka Press, New Edition, 2010)
register here against the trend of the times.
It is fashionable today to say that the law of value
is outdated. This would have been particular to the industrial manufacturing
stage of capitalism, overtaken by the formation of contemporary ‘cognitive
capitalism’. We forget
33
that, by its essential nature,
capitalism today and yesterday is based on social relations of capital
domination and the labour exploitation associated with it. It cannot be
otherwise.
The invention of the ‘cognitive capitalism’ concept lies on
the rallying to the method of orthodox economics – based on measure of specific
productivities of factors of production (labour, capital, nature, etc). We
discover that progress by these factorial productivities explains only 50 or 60
or 70 per cent of the general progress (of growth). This difference is due to
the intervention of science and technology, regarded as a fourth independent factor.
Some think they have rediscovered it in the concept of ‘human technological
creativity’ the importance of which Marx underlined in defining social labour
productivity. But there is nothing new here because work, scientific and
technical knowledge are inseparable at all stages of human history (From Capitalism to Civilization, Annex
2, pages 113 to 123). I proposed a radical criticism of the orthodox method
that I accused of artificially separating work (with the tools it uses and
under the natural conditions of its development) from scientific and technical
knowledge without which it cannot alone be considered. The operation is the
same as in theology where the soul is separated from the body (From Capitalism to Civilization, pages
77 to 84).
There is only one productivity, social labour, operating
with adequate tools, in a given natural environment, on the basis of scientific
and technical knowledge, incorporating inseparable elements. What orthodox
economics separates artificially, Marx associates, thus giving to the concept
of value that emerges its fundamental status, a condition in turn for radical
criticism of capitalist reality. Cognitive capitalism is an oxymoron. We can
only speak of ‘cognitive economy’ when social relations other than those on
which capitalism is based have been established. Instead of this vision that
the trends of the times inspires, I have tried to add the transformations of forms
of expression of the law of value that capitalist transformations entrain.
In Critique
de l’air du temps (Harmattan, 1997, Chapter V, pages 66 to 80)
I imagined a capitalism that is at the extreme
in its decline in allocated labor to material production (hardware, the
hardware store: manufactured objects and food products) by an imaginary
generalization of ‘robotisation’ production departments will only mobilise a
tiny fraction of labour force, used, on the one hand, in producing sciences and
technologies (software) for the hardware and, on the other hand, in services
associated with consumption. Under these conditions, the dominating relations
of capital, expressing itself in the unequal distribution of global income and
value, only has meaning at this integrated and comprehensive level. The concept
of value exists only because society remains alienated in economism.
34
Does the system at this stage of its development
still deserve to be called ‘capitalism’? Probably not. It could be
neo-tributary based on the exercise of a systematic political violence
(associated with ideological procedures that can give it the semblance of
legitimacy), itself essential to the reproduction of inequality. Such a system
is sadly unthinkable in a globalised scale, it is already underway. I have
described it as ‘global apartheid’. The logic of forces that command capitalist
reproduction operates in this direction, the direction that would produce
‘another possible world’, even more barbaric than have been all successive
class societies in history!
From the Law of Value to the Law of Globalised
Value
I now broach the law of
transformation of value which I think is the most important by far, in terms of
its consequences, which operate decisively in all fields of social struggles
and in all national and international political conflicts of the modern world.
I mean the transformation of value into globalised value.
I had sensed the importance of this issue even during
the writing of my doctoral thesis (in 1954-1956), although it took me ten years
to express it and to write about it, even clumsily. The issue was not brought
up by Marx. And it is, in this precise sense that I pretend – with humility –
to have
contributed in expanding and
enriching Marxism. I had, perhaps, the audacity to imagine what Book 6 of the Capital, announced in the Grundrisse under the title of
‘International Trade’, could have been. Of course what I wrote then, stems from
contemporary reality, quite different from that of Marx’s time. The thesis
barely convinced the thinkers of Western Marxism, except, to my knowledge, that
of Giovanni Arrighi. On the contrary, it was well received in Asia and Africa,
where, through diverse but ultimately converging voices, it contributed to the
shaping of an Asian and African face of Marxism.
The argument is simple, but still double. Truly
existing historical capitalism has always been imperialist in the precise sense
that the inherent mechanisms of its global development, far from gradually
homogenizing economic conditions globally, have instead produced, reproduced
and deepened the divide between the dominant (imperialist) centres and the
dominated peripheries. It is in this irregularity that is affirmed, with still
greater violence than that imagined by Marx, the law of impoverishment
inseparably associated with the logic of capital accumulation. My proposed
developments on the forms of accumulation by dispossession find their place
here.
Despite this permanent irregularity, capitalism is
one and indivisible. Capitalism is neither the United States nor Germany, while
India and Ethiopia would only be half of it. Capitalism is the United States,
India, Ethiopia and Germany put together. This means that labour force has only
one value, the one associated with the level of exploitation of productive
forces considered
35
on a global scale (the
‘general intellect’ on this scale). In response to the controversial argument
that was opposed to it – ‘how can one compare the value of working hours in The
Congo and in The United States?’ – Arghiri Emmanuel had written: ‘as we compare
the value of the working hours of the hairdresser from New York to that of the
worker in Detroit’. We need to
be consistent. One cannot invoke
inevitable globalisation when it is convenient and deny its consideration when
it disturbs!
But if there is only one value of labour force on the
level of global capitalism, this force is, nevertheless, still paid for at very
different prices. Certainly, price variations in labour force do exist in the
central capitalist countries themselves, but this variation is increased
tenfold in the world.
We can therefore model the expressions of this reality, and,
from them, measure their magnitude (if one wants to bother), that is to say
that of the transfer of value from the peripheries to the centres. This is a
transfer hidden in the system of observed prices and wages and therefore
unthinkable for the neoclassical economist. I therefore make in this way the
terms of this modelling required to understand the metamorphosis that
transforms the law of value into a law of globalised value.
A second set of arguments exists about access to natural
resources, the standards governing their management and their uses thereof.
Here, we are no longer in the law of value, but at the external borders of the
latter. This is why Marx does not confuse ‘value’ and ‘wealth’ as do all the
neoclassical economists, including supposed Marxists open to contributions from
conventional economy. Marx concludes his radical criticism of Capital by noting that capitalist
accumulation is based on the destruction of the foundations of wealth: human
beings and nature.
It took a century and half for our ecologists to
re-discover this reality that is now blinding. It is true that historical
Marxism had largely erased the analysis offered by Marx on the subject and
adopted the standpoint of the bourgeoisie – considered as a classic rational
point of view – concerning the exploitation of natural resources. So we must
now retake the issue from zero. Certainly, the bourgeois economy was forced to
consider the price of access to those of resources that are subject to private
ownership, and designed mining revenue in its own way similar to land revenue.
It is, henceforth, recognised that the challenge is at a totally different
level that must incorporate all the unprocessed resources. Neoclassical
economics is unable to do so, while the creative method of Marxism allows it.
The treatment of natural resources is inextricably linked to
the analysis of irregular globalisation produced by capitalist expansion. As
unequal access to the use of global resources is in turn a second dimension of
the imperialist rent no less important than that from the global prioritisation
of the price of labour power.
36
One or two
Models of Accumulation?
I proposed (Unequal Development, pages 60-65 and 164-169) two models of
accumulation, one for the centre and another for the periphery. The central
model is controlled by Departments I and II of Capital, which thus expresses the consistency of a self-centred
capitalist economy. On the contrary, in the peripheral model, what controls the
reproduction of the system links exports (driven) to consumption (induced). The
model is ‘extroverted’ (as opposed to ‘self-centred’). It reflects a dependency
in the sense that the periphery unilaterally adjusts to dominant trends across
the global system in which it is integrated into, these trends being themselves
controlled by the demands of accumulation at the centre.
Obviously, each of these models (central and
peripheral) passed through successive phases with their own characteristics.
For example, the peripheral model passes from the first stage (agricultural and
mineral exports) to that of industrialisation through import substitution (the
general model of the second half of the twentiethcentury, during the Bandung
era) and then to the generalised industrialisation for export competing with
industries from the centre (the Chinese model of the 1990s). However, the model
remains peripheral because it operates within unilateral adjustments to the
demands of globalisation.
These conditions that govern accumulation globally,
thus, reproduce unequal development. They explain that countries are
underdeveloped because they are overexploited and not because they are late (if
they were actually late, this allowed their overexploitation).
Experience, however, confirms this view. All
projections of dependent development policies elaborated at constant prices
lead to a blockage by the double deficit of external balance and the public
finance; all projections of these same policies elaborated ex post at current prices (relative prices of imports and exports)
lead to the same blockage even faster. This fact has only one explanation: that
price structures are distorted (as a result of combined class struggles in the
world) favouring increased exploitation in the periphery.
‘Catching up’, according to the sense that the false
theory of ‘stages of growth’ gives it, becomes impossible in the context of
truly existing capitalism, imperialist in nature. This conclusion does not only
concern the past, it questions the future under construction. The idea that
supposedly emerging countries are engaged on the road to catch up due to their
deep integration in globalisation as it is (and it cannot be otherwise) is
baseless.
The two models are none the less constitutive of one
reality that of an accumulation operating worldwide, characterised by the two
Departments I and II of Marx, retained, henceforth, at the global scale and no
more in the
37
societies of the centre. Because exports from
the periphery become at this scale constitutive elements of constant capital
and variable capital (the price of which they reduce), while imports have
similar functions to those of Department III, that is to say facilitating the
realization of surplus profit.
The conclusion I drew from the implementation of this
expression of global capitalist economy /social struggles and national and
international political conflicts, is that the North-South conflict and the conflict
between the tendency to reproduce social relations specific to capitalism on
the one hand and, in counterpoint, the demands of their socialist excess on the
other, are inseparable. The magnitude of the calculable portion of the
imperialist rent, produced by the differential in price of labour (to equal
productivity), is obviously considerable. I will attempt here to give an order
of magnitude, with the assumption that global GDP is divided into two-thirds
for the centres (20 per cent of global population) and one-third for the
peripheries (80 per cent of global population). I am assuming a growth rate of
GDP of 4.5 per cent per annum for the centres and peripheries and wage growth
at 3.5 per cent for centres and zero for peripheries (stagnant labour income).
After fifteen years of development of this system, we would achieve the results
summarized in the following table:
YEAR 1
|
Centres
|
Peripheries
|
Globe
|
GDP
|
66
|
33
|
100
|
Wages
|
33
|
17
|
50
|
Profits
YEAR 15
|
33
|
16
|
50
|
GDP
|
132
|
68
|
200
|
Wages
|
56
|
17
|
73
|
Profits
|
56
|
17
|
73
|
Department III
|
20
|
20
|
|
Imperialist rent
|
34
|
34
|
|
Of course, the volume of this imperialist
rent, which is of about half of the apparent GDP of peripheries, being 17 per
cent of global GDP or 25 per cent for the centres may be partially masked by
exchange rates. This is a well known reality that makes international
comparisons uncertain (GDP at market exchange rate or the exchange rate
ensuring equivalence of purchasing power?). Moreover, the rent is not fully
transferred to the benefit of centres. Retention of a portion by the local
ruling classes is the condition of agreement
38
for them to ‘play the game
of globalisation’. But the fact remains that the
material benefits from this rent,
that benefit not only the dominant capital on a global scale, but also the
affluent societies of the centres, are very considerable.
Calculable advantages associated with the
differential in labour pricing are added to those which are not calculable
though decisive, based on exclusive access to global resources, technological
monopolies and control of the globalised financial system.
Unequal
Access to Global Resources and the Ecological Issue
Classical economics was interested in
natural resources only when they were under private ownership. It then treated
these resources as factors of production eligible to an income (revenue)
determined by the productivity of the factor in question. In counterpoint, Marx
analyzes these revenues as categories of distribution, that is7 to say, as
taxes imposed on the profit. For natural resources do not create value,
although they are an important foundation of wealth.
The exploitation of global resources has now become
disproportionate, whether they are subject to appropriation (such as subsoil
and resources) or not (such as atmospheric air), and has brought back the issue
of treatment of natural conditions of production. Contemporary neoclassical
economics maintained its policy positions, seeking to integrate into its usual
reasoning these new factors of production to give them a price. For my part, I
see it differently and I will evoke, by prolonging without fear, the
reflections initiated by Marx. Because the emergence of these issues is
precisely the best witness to the limits that the so-called economic science
cannot cross, and calls for further consideration of the radical criticism of
both the reality that capitalism represents on the one hand and its alienated
representations through the new orthodox economics (known as ‘green’) on the
other hand.
The issue of natural resources – read
global – by its very definition
challenges the nature of the
irregular global system of truly existing capitalism / imperialism. Strategies
and practices implemented by the dominant centres work to preserve to their
benefit the exclusivity of access to these resources. The imperialist rent is
thus a second dimension, superimposed on the one drawn from the global
hierarchisation of the price of labor power.
Orthodox neoclassical economics is obsessed with the
false concept of real prices, be they those of ordinary goods, labour, money,
time, or natural resources. There are no ‘real prices’ that the ‘market’ would
have the genius of revealing. Prices are the combined products of the rates of
labour exploitation (the rate of profit), competition and split capital, and
deducted tax in the form of oligopoly revenues of political and social
conditions that control the distribution of surplus value between profits, land
and mineral revenues.
39
Mining revenues are thus determined by compromises from
the confrontation between the owners of the subsoil on the one hand and the
entire capitalist class on the other hand. Because the tax that mining revenue
represents, precisely, concerns the entire system of capital reproduction,
government intervention has always been decisive in this area. I developed my
thoughts on this question in a chapter of my book on the globalisation of the
law of value.
The ecological question requires us to leave the narrow
context of conventional economic reasoning which recognises only exchange
value, replacing it with the fantasy of an economy based on usage value, that
is to say the political economy of socialism (actually the communism of Marx).
The concept of ecological footprint,
introduced by the work of Wackernagel and Rees (Our Ecological Footprint, 1996, New Society Press) that I commented
on, moreover, started this major reflection for radical social thought on the
construction of the future, based on a calculation (and I mean a calculation
and not a speech) that itself was based on the usage value of resources of the
planet shown here by their measure in global hectares (gha), and not in
dollars.
The proof exists that the social usage value can be the
subject of perfectly rational calculations. This proof is decisive in its scope
since socialism is defined in terms of society based on usage value rather than
exchange value. While defenders of capitalism – the end of history – have
always held that socialism is an unrealistic utopia because they believe that
the usage value is not measurable, except if it matched with exchange value
(based on ‘utility’
in conventional economics).
The establishment of ecological calculation by orthodox
economics is rapidly advancing. Ecological costs are assimilated, to this
effect, into external economy. The orthodox method of calculating cost /
benefit specific to the measure of exchange value (itself confused with market
price) is then used to define a ‘fair price’ integrating economies and external
economies. Mission accomplished. The establishment of ecological discourse
through the political culture of consensus (necessary expression of the concept
of capitalism – the end of history) is no less advanced. This establishment
takes the easy path. This is because it responds to alienations and illusions
that nourish the dominant culture, which is that of capitalism. Easy because
this culture truly exists, is in place, and dominant in the minds of most
humans, in the South and in the North.
In counterpoint, the expression of the demands of the counter
culture of socialism leads to a difficult path. For the culture of socialism is
not there, before us. This culture is a future to invent, a civilization
project open to the inventive imagination. Phrases (such as ‘socialization
through democracy
40
and not through the market’,
‘dominance of culture replaced by economics and politics at its service’) are
not sufficient, despite the power that they have to begin the historical
process of change. Being a long secular process, the reconstruction of societies,
on principles different from capitalism in both North and South, is not to be
imagined fast. But the construction of the future, however distant, begins
today.
The
North-South conflict over access to global resources The issue of
‘mining revenue’, or more generally revenue that countries get from natural
resources within their territory, is inseparable from forms of domination of
oligopolistic capitalism on subordinate peripheries. The treatment of this
question is closely associated with the analysis of the phases of economic
imperialism, of international class alliances related to it, and the modalities
of labour division controlled by it. To each phase corresponds, then, a certain
simultaneous arrangement of productions and applications, a suitable structure
of income distribution: structuring of labour remuneration, amount and profit
rate, volume and rate of land revenue, volume of revenues from natural
resources.
In the first case in point, we distinguish three
phases in the evolution of capital accumulation within the imperialist system.
During the first phase (the long nineteenthcentury until the 1930s and 1960s of
the twentieth century, according to countries and regions), international
division of labour, colonialstyle, confines the periphery to the export of
agricultural and mineral products. This division of labour based on class
alliances between imperialism and the traditional local ruling classes results in
a relative price structure of goods traded globally. This leads to the
promotion of industrial capital accumulation at the centre, facilitating wage
increases parallel to the development of labour.
Price structures corresponding to this equilibrium
point to land revenues that reward landowners, allies of imperialism, but they
do not include mineral revenues, which constitute the capital that the colonial
monopolies reserve for themselves through free access to peripheral underground
resources while confining the new comprador classes of dominated regions to its
purchasing portion. We often forget that the easy growth of the ‘thirty
glorious years’ (1945-1975) was associated with energy prices (particularly
petrol)
reduced to almost zero.
The second phase of modern unequal globalisation
opens with the victories of national liberation movements in Asia and in
Africa, during the Bandung era (1955-1980) and the development of the
Non-Aligned Movement. This second phase is characterised by import substitution
industrialisation. This requires the renewal of international class alliances,
the replacement of the national bourgeoisie with the old ruling classes.
41
During this phase, the dynamic balance continues to
operate primarily on the basis of the expansion of centre markets, fuelled by
wage growth, exacerbated by the maintenance of unequal exchange rates, with the
periphery continuing to provide raw materials under conditions of stagnant
labour wages, while its earnings pay for imports of industrial goods and equipment
which replace previously imported consumer goods. Land revenues sometimes
disappear when feudal alliances are broken through bourgeois agrarian reforms
that establish new classes of landowners and middle peasants. Consequent
reduction in agricultural prices favours the local bourgeoisies engaged in
substitution industrialisation as it favours oligopolistic imperialism, in a
context whereby agricultural products continue to be exported to the centre.
However, whatever the limitations of this first moment of
awakening would have been, the on-going movement of peoples and nations in
Bandung soon raised the issue of acquired income by states concerned about
their natural resources. Bandung proclaimed the principle of the exercise of
national sovereignty over those resources and succeeded, albeit belatedly – in
1973 –
in imposing an upward revision of oil
prices as we know.
This readjustment of access conditions to natural
resources (oil price is a symbol) was not inherently anti-capitalist. On the
contrary, the inclusion of revenues (oil in this case) in the prices of natural
resources exported by the South would have improved capital mobilisation by the
peripheral bourgeoisie which in turn would have allowed them to enter into a
new era of industrialisation, based this time on the export of industrial
products to the centres. The relocation of some industries, from the North,
could have recreated an unemployment reserve account, which would have
simultaneously helped in raising profit rate. Expansion would have been
initiated through the export industry of the South, on the basis of which, new
motor industries could resume their expansion in the North. This perspective,
quite capitalist in nature, to overcome the contradictions of the global
system, was the programme of the peripheral bourgeoisie of the time. The
imperialist West rejected the proposals and adjustments were finally made of
the ‘New International Economic Order’, even though oil price was imposed. Very
different theses have been proposed on this subject. Some have focused on the
objective economic conditions of energy production: trend reversal on the
relative price of oil, for example, which, falling for a century, would have
begun a long period of recovery from the 1960s to 1970s. Others have emphasised
the inter-imperialist contradictions and stressed the United States’ commitment
to turn in their favour a deteriorating situation
(dollar crisis, etc), while mobilizing
oil multinationals and petro-states against Europe and Japan. Some even went
further and saw in this last conspiracy a
42
manifestation of the strategy of
multinationals that would have chosen alliance with Third World states against
the central states. The objective of multinationals was supposedly to increase
profit rates through the relocation of industries under their control.
Adjustments in the economies of the North made to
absorb oil price shocks actually inspired strategies to enable capital to go on
the offensive and dismantle the gains of the working classes (post-war social
democratic compromise). These strategies succeeded in imposing on these working
classes the needed restructuring for the resumption of accumulation that was
grounded. The new order project was then finally implemented (relocations as
proof). But it was neither under peripheral bourgeoisie control nor their
states’ control – nor to their benefit – as elaborated in the original project.
It was in fact implemented for the benefit of oligopoly capital of the
imperialist centres! This operation opened the – short – era of new
globalisation called ‘neo-liberalism’ that I qualified as the second ‘golden
age’. The fast and expected ‘breathlessness’ of this phase of globalisation
created conditions for a ‘second wave of awakening of the South’, initiated
even before the 2008 financial collapse.
The ruling classes and the states of the
South – at least those qualified as ‘emerging’ – retook the initiative and
engaged in accelerated industrialisation and ‘modernisation’ of their
agriculture. The pursuit of their business requires that these countries
benefit from an increasing access to global natural resources, which arises
when the operating costs of the best of these scarce resources, are
considerably higher than in the past. Beyond these cost issues, the battle is
now engaged on the ground for direct access to resources. Western imperialism
intends to reserve them for itself – a condition for the continuation of its
‘lifestyle’ and the basis of a social consensus that guarantees the stability
of capital power – through brutal global military control. This
North-South conflict has therefore
become the major conflict of our time.
The range of natural resources in question is broader
than was previously thought, not long ago. It concerns oil and gas, but also
the rare minerals, water and agricultural land – whose access has become the
stake in conflicts over their use – and even the atmosphere (and through it,
the climate).
Under these conditions, it is impossible to resolve
the issue of determining mining revenue (or more generally the access cost of
the resources in question) in general terms. Examination of this issue must be
based on concrete analyses of concrete situations. For each mineral, specific
circumstances control the debate over its revenue, and possible outcome. Thus,
as a comparative example, one could cite the case of iron ore, long produced
exclusively in developed countries for their national steel industry. Since
steel needs were no longer being satisfied by former major producers, the West
secured, for itself, a mining belt of safe countries (Canada, Brazil, South
Africa and
43
Australia) to provide competitive
minerals in largely sufficient quantities in the foreseeable future. Under
these conditions, Third World producers (Venezuela, Mauritania, Guinea,
Liberia, Gabon, India, and Malaysia) are marginalised and deprived of
negotiation possibilities (particularly if Brazil continues to refuse them
support). But, on the other hand, the financial requirements for the
establishment of steel plants in Third World countries are considerable. Here
we can see the possibility for a three-partner association: the Third World
steelmakers, countries with significant financial resources (the OPEC
countries, China, Japan, etc.) and countries with mining resources. Such an
association would strengthen the collective autonomy of these countries and
separate the minerals/steel relationship between the periphery and the centre,
that is still exerting influence on the mining and steel producing countries of
the Third World. Mineral revenues, within this context, would become negotiable
between States.
Revenue utilisation by countries that are
potential beneficiaries obviously
depends on the type of dominant ruling
classes in place. In extreme cases – still frequent – this revenue may be
wasted by the ruling cliques to solely maintain their stay in power, with
neither the masses nor even the country benefiting from it (this revenue is not
invested in economic development). In other cases – as in the Gulf countries –
this revenue simply funds the globalised financial market controlled by Western
oligopolies. These patterns of revenue utilisation by dependent states or
powerless archaic regimes are quite acceptable to the dominant economic
imperialism. On the contrary, when the revenue is used for development, be it
capitalist – as in emerging countries – conflict becomes inevitable. Is Imperialist Revenue Called into Question?
The visible part of imperialist revenue
– that comes from the structuring of labour price – is already huge by itself,
and measurable, if one bothers to find out. This can be confiscated by the
countries of the South only to the extent whereby they ‘disconnect’– even
relatively – to give priority to domestic market development and to the
satisfaction of the needs of their masses. Only then can this anti-imperialist
position help in bringing focus on surpassing capitalist social relations and
engaging on the long road to socialism.
The invisible part of capitalist revenue – access to global
resources – though not measurable (being outside the scope of economy), is no
less important. The battle here is on the affirmation of sovereignty of the
countries of the South on these resources, together with their assignment to
give priority to internal development. Through this option, the countries of
the South would refuse to submit to the perspective of global apartheid, which
capitalist logic imposes.
44
By engaging in these directions, the victories of
the nations of the South would be the conditions for questioning the consensus
based on profits derived, by the North, through capitalist revenue. Progress in
the South depends on the defeat of capitalist states through confrontation with
the nations of the North.
Market Alienation and Financialisation, the two
Inseparable Dimensions of Capitalism
Capitalism is a social system – the
first – whereby economic authority directly dominates all other authorities of
social life. In other words, ‘economic life’ now directly dominates other
aspects of social life. The economy is more than ‘important ultimately’. Having
won its autonomy, economic life is then subjected to its own laws, and to
discover its outlines can and should therefore become the subject of a
particular scientific thinking. This is the purpose of the new economic
science, that it is best to call political economy to highlight the
relationship that associates its autonomy to the new historical/political stage
that is capitalism.
It is, thus, no coincidence that economic
science began its first formulations at the time of the Enlightenment, in close
relation with the emergence of the discourse of bourgeois ideas. This social
class – the bourgeoisie – is then in conflict with the existing order, that of
the Old Regime.
Bourgeois enlightenment thought
inaugurates modernity that I defined as the proclamation that man makes his own
history, in contrast with the dominant conception of earlier times, based on
the idea that it is God, or the gods, through the ancestors that created an
unchangeable social order. Bourgeois thought flushes out alienation (therefore
irrationality) that underlies this submission to the demands of the existing
order, the alienation that I qualified as metaphysical specific to dependent
production methods. The criticism that this thought directs to the system
governing reality and the beliefs of the Old Regime seeks to be scientific. And
it is, once one understands that science is neither final, nor complete. The
system of organisation of real economic and social life that the rising
bourgeoisie proposes, and the system of thought that accompanies it and gives
it legitimacy, are based on the concept of rationality that defines the entire
scope of the thought on Enlightenment.
The contradictory, limited and ambiguous nature of
modernity and the new rationality is expressed through the conviction of the
bourgeoisie that the new system it wishes to promote, that is to say,
capitalism (in the sense of capitalist relations of production), is simply an
expression of complete, definitive, rationality and not of the relative
rationality associated with capitalism. The scientific nature of the analyses
that the new political economy
45
proposes, is, therefore, contradictory,
limited, not completed (as the bourgeoisie believes). The legitimising function
of the established new capitalist order, and bourgeois political economy of
Enlightenment is inseparable from its methods, conceptualisations and from the
economic laws that they help in elaborating.
So let us step back and look at capitalism not as the end of
the story (which the thought on Enlightenment cannot afford to doubt), but as a
stage in an uncompleted story. It then becomes clear that, to do this, it is
necessary to make the double radical criticism of the real world (defined
mainly by capitalist economy) and the thought that grants it absolute
legitimacy – without time limit. That is to say, criticism of labour
exploitation by capital (on which the system is based) and criticism of
bourgeois political economy.
Marx focused on doing this. And he did it with
unparalleled convincing power. Reading of Capital
enables one to understand the immense scope of this double criticism of real-world
labour exploitation and bourgeois economic science that masks its reality.
To do this, Marx attacks the
formulations of the new political economy – the most serious, the closest to
science – those of Adam Smith and David Ricardo. This does not prevent him, in
passing, to criticise – sometimes in humorous style as it should be – the first
visions of the economics of his
time (Bastiat, Say, et al).
Indeed, the moment completed capitalism is established with
the emergence of the machine invented by the industrial revolution, bourgeois
thought ceases to be critical, as it was obliged to be in its fight against the
now toppled Old Order. The dimension through which it legitimates the new order
wins the day. The scientific spirit that it evoked in its criticism of the old
order no longer has a raison d’être.
The history of economic science – now
bourgeois (in that Marx gives this qualification to its legitimizing function
of the capitalist order) – becomes the story of its vision, of its increasingly
marked distancing from the basic requirements of scientific thought.
To delegitimise this pseudo-science called
(modern) ‘economic science’
becomes an essential requirement in the
exercise of the ability to criticise reality, and formulate objectives from
this criticism in the fight to change the way.
We will draw the outlines of this criticism, without
which the views on building another world (supposedly better, of course) become
wishful thinking and baseless. We will do this in stages. We recall, first, the
basis of the criticism of neoclassical economics post-Marxist (actually
anti-Marxist). We continue with a presentation on various aspects and degrees
of alienation that are specific to capitalism. This presentation will allow you
to flush out
46
the aberration of contemporary
discourses (including the left) on financialisation and, in connection with it,
the nature of the ongoing crisis of contemporary capitalism.
Criticism of Orthodox Neoclassical Economics and
its Avatars from the Left
After Marx, to go against his views
and discoveries, serious bourgeois economy tries to develop a counter proposal
based on a positivist / empiricist method that is allegedly similar to a
scientific method. Walras in the nineteenth century and Sraffa in the twentieth
(but also Keynes) are the major thinkers – consistent and firm – that
illustrate better than others this attempt to analyze the functioning of the
reality (capitalist) without turning to the concepts highlighted by Marx’s
discoveries (the law of value).
I, therefore, focus my criticism of conventional
economics on these thinkers.
The starting point for Walras, Sraffa and Keynes is
in the rejection of the law of value,under the pretext that the transformation
of values into costs of production was ‘impossible’, or at least unnecessary
and cumbersome. I will not repeat what I said about this: that this refusal
demonstrates the inability of these thinkers to understand alienation.
Walras – and after him, Sraffa – therefore
consider (wrongly) the value
(work) as a metaphysical and
cumbersome hypothesis. But they are not any further won over to its substitutes
– the value / usefulness – that they probably judge as also metaphysical. They,
then, stick to the immediate visible reality of – market prices. Walras
proposes in this strict positivist spirit a model of generalised
interdependence, coded in a system of equations describing the production of n
products as it is, that is to say from inputs of equipment, raw materials and
direct labour. These inputs are quantifiable by the technical coefficients that
define implemented methods of production The system solution correctly provides
products prices under certain conditions. First, the system does not classify
the productions into the two departments similar to those considered by Marx.
Walras’s system does not tell us, then, if the volume of profits from
production will be lower, equal, or greater than that required to be allocated
to investment (in equipment) necessary in the production of consumer goods that
correspond to effective demand (determined by the fraction of net proceeds
assigned to this demand for consumer goods). The question is not by Walras. So,
he does not answer it. However, to understand the possibility and reality of
accumulation we are, actually, forced to answer this question.
Then – and here is the major criticism
against the Walras model of general equilibrium – it is not established that
the application of a decentralised market
47
solution actually provides the solution
that can de deduced from the system of n equations, even by trial and error.
For, when a single agent takes any decision (e.g., to change the technical mode
of production) the system, in its entirety, is transformed and its solution
yields results different from those of the system in place prior to this
decision. The system then moves into reality from imbalance to imbalance (due
to the decisions taken) never aiming at a balance. The history of the system
triumphs over the rationality of its solution!
Walras was honest – a quality certainly alien to today’s
Nobel Prize winners – and therefore acknowledged this failure. The failure of
positivism as a scientific method? Walras did not dare go that far; to
acknowledge the scientific superiority of Marx’s method and the inevitability
of the law of value and the consideration of the rate of surplus value (degree
of labour exploitation). Value/labour then appears not as a metaphysical
hypothesis but as an expression of acknowledgement of reality. It is known that
Walras has imagined only one solution to the problem: entrance of an
‘auctioneer’ who knows everything in advance: the invisible hand, or God, which
exists only for those who believe. Contemporary neoclassical economics will
substitute it with the ‘perfect foresight’ of those officers (plural) gifted
with a perfect knowledge of the objective requirements of the operation of the
system – a terminology substituted with another,
which adds nothing to it.
Neoclassical economics, committed to the path of the
analysis of markets operating on the basis of an imperfect information, is then
forced to substitute the analysis of capitalist reality with an endless game
(in which mathematics becomes indispensable) of assumptions about expectations.
For the assumptions about expectations help to pre-empt everything and nothing,
which Keynes’ subtle and realistic intelligence had fully grasped.
What expectations? A series of good jokes. The
expectations of labour sellers? The unfortunate know they have little choice.
They also know that they can only improve the sale of their labour through
organisation and collective class struggle. Like consumers who choose (their
supermarket?) and choose their prospective financial investments? The
unfortunates are indeed forced to go with the advice of their bankers, the real
decision makers. Those of entrepreneurs who decide to invest or not to? History
shows, as Marx and Keynes had understood it, that the cycles of
over-investment, then of capital depreciation impose their reality. That of
capital owners who choose between risky term investments and liquidity
preference? The recurring story of financial bubbles of which the reasons and
mechanisms have been fully analysed, once again, by Marx, together with his
discovery of the supreme alienation of neoclassical economics ‘money makes
money’, A gives A
‘without going through
production’, will always remain outside the scope of
48
thought of our conventional
economists. And that of stock market speculators? We know that the best
position is the one taken by the sheep that follow the general trend and that
this practice necessarily increases the magnitude of instability.
Drowning in the ocean of expectations is the
inevitable product of the reduction of society to a sum of individuals and to a
wilful ignorance of major realities through which is defined real capitalism
(the classes, private property, the State, nations, etc...). This is an
ideological expression in the negative sense of the term, which is perfectly in
place to give legitimacy to the actual practices of dominant capital. The
neoclassical economists who lay claim to scientific work are not even aware of
this. They cannot understand that to do scientific work, to approach an
understanding of objective reality, we must start from the radical criticism of
the starting point of their reasoning.
Walras concludes, then, that capitalism can only work
if it is no longer capitalism, but a planned system (by the State, as the only
capitalist). Walras was a socialist, just like his pupil Barone, the ancestor
of Gosplan. And the Gosplan projects not a socialist economy, but – in the
historical settings of the Soviet Union – a capitalist economy without
capitalists. The model of general equilibrium, which does not reflect the real
operation of capitalism, becomes a good planning tool, that is to say a primer
establishment of a system that could pave the way (I mean just clear the way)
to the gradual replacement of socialisation through the market of a
socialisation via democracy, which requires more than good management from the
top of the productive system.
Sraffa takes back the questions by Walras and treats
them in the same way. I cannot come back here to the analyses that I devoted to
the failure of Sraffa (with some details in my book on the globalization of
value).
In line with the efforts and failures of post-Marxian
positivist economists, the economic vision starts in another direction, by
replacing utility value with labour value (Menger, von Mises and latest – the
most extremist – Von Hayek, all Austrians). And it is in this context that
originates the formless body of alleged contemporary economic science, on the
one hand, and the recovery and takeover of Keynes, on the other hand, by the
new economic termed ‘neoclassical’ (that it is not, having failed from the
beginning with the classics).
The construction lies in abolishing the
concept of capitalism and replacing
it with the insipid discourse on
market economy. The essential reality – which is the social relations of
production (especially the private ownership of means of production becoming,
thus, capital) – is excluded quickly. We feign ignorance that the markets in
question must be qualified and are actually
49
capitalist markets – that is
to say, subject to the requirements of capital
appreciation.
This abolition of the concept of capitalism rests on two
assumptions apparently unrelated to reality.
Firstly, we substitute the relations of production –
particularly the submission of the seller of labour to the employer forced to
appreciate capital – with the assumption of a society made up of individuals,
who ultimately become the active agents of the reproduction system and its
evolution. This individual (Robinson or the homo
economicus) is non-historical, identical to himself since the dawn of
humanity. Similarly, ecological challenges are formulated in terms of relations
between Man and Nature, without reference to the economic and social system in
which the man in question thinks and acts. Capitalism and the capitalist are
thus freed from all suspicion.
Secondly, the concept of capital itself is abolished.
Standard neoclassical economics recognizes only equipment (with their own
productivity) implemented by work. Another non-historical concept since, of all
times, the worker has used instruments, the peasant plough, the artisan’s
medieval tools, the bow and the arrow of the first hunter and even before him
carved, then polished stones of homo
sapiens of archaeological periods. At this rate, capitalism, though
confused with the use of means of production, always existed. The construction
built on these foundations – the market economy – does not correspond to a
stylized expression of the world of historical and real capitalism. This is the
construction of an imaginary system that only integrates the essence of what
characterises the capitalist reality. Consequently, some major and decisive
dimensions of reality, such as the domination of monopolies in the entire
production system (and the issue of increasing returns associated with it) can
also be deliberately ignored.
Modern conventional economy has never been able to render
operational the economic system imagined by it on these bases. I refer the
reader, here, to Rémy Herrera (Another
Capitalism is Not Possible, Syllepse, 2010) who made the thorough proof of
this. From Walras to Solow and Samuelson, to Debreu and Arrow, there is a
failed attempt to prove that the convergence of agents’ choices is visible,
recognised, but without any conclusion drawn from it. The solution requires
that we replace the multiplicity of agents, with the single representative
agent (i.e., one who knows everything – Big Brother, the Auctioneer of Walras,
the planner of Gosplan, or the invisible hand of...God!). There are no more
interactive Robinsons, but one Robinson who represents all! There is no field
of scientific research–beyond economic science – where such nonsense would be
tolerated.
50
Neoclassical economics is not a standalone
product borne from intellectual and academic delirium. It occupies an important
place in the ideological construction essential to capitalism – and often, more
brutally and like today – serves as a screen for covering the most undemocratic
and deliberately
reactionary policies.
The utility value has this unparalleled virtue that
helps to erase the idea that the submission of labour to capital can be the
vehicle for the exploitation of workers. The method of analysis of society in
terms of an aggregate of individuals and the substitution of equipment with the
concept of capital (a specific social relationship) – two non-historical
operations – that allow to read the story like that a linear development /
progress. And since our contemporary societies are visibly richer than those
that preceded them, we live in a perfect world in which there can be no
question of invalidating its legitimacy, rationality, or even eternity.
The views on neoclassical economics reinforce the
ideological requirements of production and reproduction of truly existing
capitalism. It promotes at centre stage the exclusive praise of competition
regarded as the prerequisite for progress, a quality denied to solidarity
(despite historical evidence), itself locked in straitjacket compassion and
charity. Whether it concerns competition between producers (capitalists,
without much attention to the oligopolistic form of contemporary capitalist
production), or even between workers (which implies that the unemployed, or
poor, is responsible for his situation), the new language (social partners
instead of classes in conflict) like practices, amongst others, of the Court of
the European Union staunch supporter of union busting, barrier to competition
between workers) – reinforces the exclusivity of competition.
In turn, the adoption of the exclusive principle of
competition invites society to rally around the goal of building a consensus
that excludes, from perspective, an imaginary other society based on
solidarity. This ideology of a consensual society that is now about to be
adopted in Europe destroys the transformative scope of the democratic message.
It conveys the libertarian message of the right that considers the State –
whatever it is – as the enemy of freedom (read: the enemy of the enterprising
freedom of capital). It separates the practice of castrated democracy from
social progress.
The theory is called ‘economics’, as we
say ‘physics’, to show that it is not a social thought, but a hard science. Its
function is to make us believe that the markets produce by themselves the best
of worlds, or the social optimum! It invents, for this purpose, imaginary
theories – expounded without basis on the analysis of reality in its essential
and determinant scopes – to consolidate the commitment to the idea – false – on
the reign of universal
51
harmonies, that symbolise the real
prices of all : goods, money (interest rates), land and nature (externalities)
and even exchange rates that govern international relations and govern
capitalist globalisation, thus becoming also in themselves factors of
globalised, generalised progress. Deconstruction of these imaginary theories is
the starting point of the radical criticism of capitalism, needed to delegitimize
it. Some have done it within the strict domain of economic theory. Others went
beyond refusing to separate the economic (then called apolitical) from the
social and the political. This has always been the case of Marxists, but also
of others, such as Braudelians, particularly in areas concerning the
globalisation of capitalism. The economist discourse of universal harmonies
could bring others to memory, such as the Confucian discourse of ‘harmonious
development’, yet of a much better intellectual performance. But this is not
enough. We must delegitimise the bourgeois thought – henceforth reactionary by
nature – in its entirety and for that, delegitimise neoliberal economics – at
the service of the reactionary policies of capital – also as a whole. And we
are very few
addressing ourselves to this task.
Alongside genuine mathematicians (especially Israel and Guerrien), I will
mention here the recent work of Rémy Herrera, who had the bright idea to label
as science fiction the false economic science known as neoclassical, and to
demonstrate that this is so. For my part, I had used the expression ‘science of
imaginary economy’ (having nothing to do with real capitalism). I had compared
the type of questions it poses to those previously discussed by the medieval
scholars (the sex of angels). I had compared these functions with those of
witchcraft in ancient times (Critique de
l’air du temps).
The direct political function of contemporary neoclassical
economics is obvious. Its theorists are equally activists of neo-liberalism, of
often the far right. Their major concern is to justify reactionary (State)
policies to the extreme, with the real purpose of supporting the growth of
social inequalities. Brave moralists, addressing themselves to the
complementary tasks of ‘fight against poverty’, that provide them with useful
alibis. Internationally, these neoliberal theorists advocate the destruction of
the State in the peripheries of the system, paving the way for the return of
colonialism for which they never lost the nostalgia.
Undoubtedly, sincere reformers though too timid to challenge
the social relations characteristic of capitalism, or even the contemporary
dominance of oligopolies, believe they can give capitalism a human face. Obama
was elected proclaiming ‘Yes we can’. The title of his next Speech of the Union
should be ‘No, we cannot’, and thereby recognize that it is the oligopolies and
not the elections that are at the controls. When the question was put to
52
Paul Sweezy, ‘What would
you do if the President were to put you at the head of the FED?’ (the Central
Bank in the US), his answer was: ‘Resign’. Rémy Herrera is right, ‘another
capitalism is not possible’ (title of his book).
Delegitimizing both the system (truly existing
capitalism in the era of globalised, financialised and generalised oligopolies
in the terminology I proposed) and its intellectual mode of legitimacy
(especially by neoclassical economics) is not easy. The task is made more
difficult presently by the adhesion of the vast majority of left thinkers to
the postulations of both standard neoclassical economics and political thought
of consensus called ‘democratic’ (in the strict sense of membership to the form
of procedural, representative electoral democracy considered final).
The contemporary left – in its majority and even
beyond the majority which the social liberalism parties represent – is
eclectic. It thinks it can combine fragments of Marxism its adherence to the postulations and the
method of conventional economic theory. The list of avatars of the left of
economic science fiction is long. I will return to some of their illustrations
on the crisis and financialisation.
The general public and the working classes are thus
disarmed, stripped of needed intellectual resources to enable their struggles
(that do exist) to assert themselves through strongrevolutionary advances,
capable of reducing their vulnerability. Yet in moments of crisis like ours,
the powerlessness of neoclassical economics appears in all its fullness.
The newspaper Le
Monde asked a mean question to this effect, ‘How is it that the “geniuses”
at Harvard did not foresee the crisis ...?’ Are they just idiots? Certainly
not. But their intelligence is entirely focused on the only tracks marked out
by neoclassical economics and the false theory of imaginary capitalism of
generalised markets. Just like the best minds of the past believed that the
debate on the sex of angels could help in better understanding the world! For
the general public, including the working classes, the big names of economic
science – recognised with the Nobel Prize (Economics) – are surrounded by a
halo of respect. They know. If, moreover, they accompany their incomprehensible
technical sentences with moralizing sentences and expressions on social issues,
the authority of their proposals hold sway.
It is time to delegitimise the Nobel Prize that is
awarded to only faithful servants of capital for their work that is not done to
enlighten but to plunge one into darkness. The Nobel Prize is the equivalent of
the Academic Prize in Painting in the nineteenth century, which rewarded the
highly placed provided they represented the Emperor or a Princess in their best
clothes ... Their names are all forgotten today. And it is those in the ‘Salon
des Independants’ who eventually prevailed. Conventional economists are not
critical thinkers.
53
They are, at best,
technocrats. I prefer to use, for them, the Anglo-Saxon term of – ‘executive’
(executing agent, here at the orders of capital, today
oligopolies).
That is why the criticisms that they can make against
the system are still marginal and reform proposals they believe are realistic
but are actually quite unrealistic for the most part. And if then, for any
moral reason they dislike the reality (‘too much poverty’ even ‘too much
inequality’), the slipping towards wishful thinking and preaching as a policy
becomes inevitable. A bestseller for a Nobel Prize winner in economics
(restricted to neoclassical economists) is therefore necessarily a work, at
best, mediocre. Joseph Stiglitz’s first chapter in his book, Making Globalization Work (Norton 2006)
that bears the pompous title ‘Another World is Possible’ is a good example of
this.
Stiglitz discovers in 2002 that the Washington Consensus
was not good; he discovers the reality of the IMF and of WTO attitudes, etc.
More than half of the 550 pages of this bloated book is celeb revelations
already known by others for the last 30 or 40 years! Stiglitz believes to be
the first to say this, having never read the work of critical thinkers (and he
will probably never read them). This has nothing here to do with arrogance, but
simply ignorance. An amusing example: Stiglitz ‘discovers’ that in 1990, there
was agreement on some prices by some oligopolies! Wonderful! And what does he
propose to restore the competition: an anti-trust law and recourse to the
courts, US style! In this work published in 2002, Stiglitz ignores
financialisation, which he says almost nothing about, that he considers
harmless and even useful ... The outstanding work of the late Giovanni Arrighi,
on financialisation as final stage of declining hegemonies, is completely
ignored. Obviously, Stiglitz was surprised by the financial collapse of 2008,
although not a line of his book indicates the seriousness of the threat. Yet,
over the same period, others (including myself) had analysed the globalised
liberal system as inherently unstable, doomed to collapse through financial crisis
(the Achilles heel of the system as I wrote). Stiglitz obviously knows nothing
about it. The idea he has of himself, revealing to the world the defects of the
system, can only be funny.
It will not be surprising that what I called the
Stiglitz report, that is to say that of the Commission designated by the
Chairman of the UN General Assembly – Padre Miguel D’Escoto – of which the
presidency was
unfortunately assigned to Stiglitz, who
probably imposed his superficial and limited perception of the problems in
finalising the document, did not move away from the scope of reactionary
conventional orthodoxy. The failure that resulted from this – the fact that
developing countries had given up on being represented at the Assembly by
officials at the required level – is in fact, for 54 me, a good sign. It
suggests that developing countries have understood that this report – under the
pretext of ‘global consensus’ ... and realism – was part of the strategy of the
North of a response to the crisis and that their proposals were likely to be
acceptable to the oligopolies. Change the world? You bet!
Market Alienation, Reification of Social Relations and Financialisation
are Inseparable
1.
Alienation is conjugated in the plural,
echoing the diversity of situations inwhich it is expressed. But there is a
common denominator to all these situations, the denominator that legitimates
the choice of this same term. There is alienation when a human being –
individually, or a society (an organized group of people) submit their views and
choices of action to what they believe to be transcendental supernatural
forces, which act on them. Alienation is thus the obstacle that emancipation –
which defines modernity (the human being is his story) – must find and analyse
in order to be able to overcome it, to destroy its binding power. This is the
freedom of thought and action to which emancipation calls and which is
unlimited. Marx himself said that men make their story, but in objective
conditions which apply to them. Freedom enables knowledge of necessities. I
will not go further in this philosophical debate – concerning ‘free will’ –
which is not my field. I will only say that in an alienated society, alienation
is itself part of the conditions that limit its thinking ability, to imagine and
to act. To delegitimise a system of thought and of action (here that of
capitalism) is doomed to failure if the alienation (or alienations) specific to
this system are not uprooted and deconstructed. Only then can we transcend them
and open wider horizons to thought and to action.
2.
The anthropological debate raises an
inevitable question: is the human being, beyond historical determinants which
condition him not, by nature, producer and victim of an alienation that he
cannot do without to live?
This debate is not ours here. Although I have
accepted, without much hesitation, that the answer to this question might
validate the saying that: the abolition of alienation is impossible for humans;
for example, in accepting the idea that man[generic] is a metaphysical animal
that cannot avoid questioning the meaning of life, even if he cannot respond to
the questions of science. Psychoanalysts do not imagine an unalienated human
being and do not imagine that we can understand his condition differently. They
may have a point.
Our discussion is more limited in scope. It involves
specific forms of alienation produced by a defined social / historical system
that conditions its functioning and reproduction. These alienations, I contend,
can be discovered through critical analysis of the system in question. Their
questioning then
55
becomes possible, necessary for going
beyond what the system allows, to innovate.
3.
I have personally taken on the task of
identifying social alienations (that is how I qualified them in contrast to
anthropological alienations) of ancient and modern times. I intended to show
here the differences (and not the similarities) between what I called
‘dependent alienation’ and ‘capitalist alienation’.
The
thesis I have proposed for this purpose is that the overthrow of the dominant
body – the power in dependent stages of civilisation, the economy in capitalism
– implied a parallel revolution in content and form of expression
of the social alienation peculiar to the
reproduction of involved systems.
I do recall here this thesis, whose follow-up is
centred exclusively on the specific alienations of capitalism.
4.
The terms ‘market alienation’ and ‘economic
alienation’ were henceforthrendered common in all schools of thought somewhat
critical of capitalist modernity, for better (for critical intent) and for the
worst (to blur the definition used by each and everyone).
The discourse on (and against) market
alienation expresses protests against
the transformation of everything into goods –
the most trivial productions, works of art, labour, scientific research, etc...
– expressed in the refusal to see the range of practice extended unceasingly
through the abolition of the concepts of public services, for example (and
their privatization). However, only the most radical protesters connect this
dominance of goods to the endless value of capital that defines capitalism.
Others believe they can say ‘yes’ to market economy and ‘no’ to the market
society. This separation is, on the contrary, impossible, for me.
The term ‘economic alienation’ is somewhat
trivial, though often expressed, rather quickly. We, express, by this, a
refusal to accept that all choices – political and social – must obey economic
imperatives. The ambiguity that this refusal projects must be lifted. In
capitalism – in its real operation and in the system of ideas that gives it
legitimacy – economics and politics are subordinated to it.
For capitalism is not to be reduced to a ‘market
economy’ I said. It is an economy of capitalist markets subject to the
requirements of capital appreciation. Thus alienation (or alienations) that
portray it cannot be reduced to the general concept of market alienation.
5.
The expression of capital appreciation does not make sense if we do not
understand the sense that Marx makes of capital and of the relations of
production associated with it.
56
Capital is neither a ‘thing’ (nor a set of equipment,
nor a monetary fortune) but a social relation. The one that requires the seller
of ‘free’ labour with nothing else to offer, to sell this labour to his
employer, landlord (or owner or manager) with the means of appreciating this
labour. This relation exists only under capitalism, and even if marginal and
embryonic forms of it appeared in ancient times, it only became dominant with
advanced capitalism.
It is in capitalism that ‘equipment’ becomes capital.
Because the social relationship then allows the exploitation of work, that is
to say, the production of a profit (the excess in the amount of work supplied –
8 hours – over that required for the reproduction of labour – for example, if
four hours are needed to produce what the employee will be allowed to consume,
to buy in the consumer goods market). Of course, only the concept of value
helps to capture the key importance of what the capitalist production relation
produces. But, I already said, bourgeois thought does not know – refuses to
know – the concept of production relation and that of value. It replaces them
with the plurality of inputs to simplify direct labour and equipment.
Capitalist thought well qualifies them as capital, but it is then with a
different meaning, that of ‘effective and useful things’ that equipment is.
Alienation proceeds here through a reification of
social relations: two things face to face, direct labour, equipment. Each of
these things has its own productivity, that of work, that of capital. I will
not repeat what this dissociation expresses – the disembodied soul as scholasticism
imagined it. For Marx – and in reality, it must be emphasized – work and work
tools are inseparable. There is only one productivity, the productivity of
labour supported with necessary tools for the accomplishment of its tasks. I
will not go back to the inconsistency of bourgeois discourse on the
‘productivity of capital’, this factor consisting of an addition of specific
equipment (and each having its own productivity). Their aggregate is impossible
outside of the common denominator that the estimation of their value (in the
trivial sense, their price) allows to establish. In other words, there is only
financialised capital (I will return to this issue). Reification of components
of the production system, separated from each other, should be continued beyond
what I have just said.
Labour productivity armed with adequate
instruments also depends on ‘natural conditions’ of production. Marx rejects
this account of the theory
of value (real, not imaginary) by
distinguishing value from wealth. Neoclassical economic thought ignores this
distinction and is therefore working and attempting to reify nature, seeing it
as a series of things that have their own productivity, as well as their price.
57
Of course, the adequacy of equipment put in place is not
separable from technological knowledge (and behind them, science). Here again,
what Marx associates (body and soul), scholasticism dissociates: science is in
turn treated as a thing that has its own productivity.
The definition of capital so reified can be changed.
Conventional economic thought replaces its definition in terms of social
relations with another reversed definition based on what its exploitation
produces: its income (profit). The operation is financial; it assumes an
interest rate (of capitalisation) and therefore the capitalisation of income at
this rate. We arrived at alienation to the power 2; exceeding that which the
mere thought of markets alienation permits to imagine.
6.
Market alienation, in general, dominates all
minds. All were struck by it, like the plague, even if all are not dead. The
worker that sells his labour power believes he is selling his work. He
therefore accepts his salary as normal pay for what he offers. At most, he
demands a just wage, a better one, and does not consider himself exploited
other than when he is overexploited. The criticism that Lenin was making in the
face of the powerlessness of the immediate consciousness – conveyed by trade
unionism – places emphasis on the effects of this alienation, and rightly so.
The most extremist lovers of the market did not hesitate
in extending the logic of supply and demand to all areas of social life, beyond
the economic. They do not hesitate in analysing, in these miserable terms, the
choice of partners in marriage, electoral choices in politics! The
excessiveness moves to talking about human capital, which reveals the
transformation of the human being into a thing regarded as such – useful – for
some in certain conditions.
7.
Money and credit certainly existed long
before capitalism. They areinseparable from exchange of goods, even at early
stages of its appearance. But with capitalism, and therefore capitalist
exchange of goods (non-goods simply), they change nature. Non-financialised
capitalism is unthinkable. Not considering that the first forms of money have
been associated with the choice of goods, produced like others, by social work.
The moment this good becomes the universal equivalent in trading, it acquires a
new nature: it becomes more than a good. But it is not yet capital. We will
need to wait for capitalism (and capital appreciation) for a sum of money to
become the equivalent of the possession of capital; that is to say precisely of
a right that renders its value possible.
In dependent societies, gold is certainly already
currency in the sense of an instrument of exchanges, of general equivalence, a
reserve of value and of liquidity. But it is especially treasure and not
capital. Those in power accumulated it not to capitalise it but to spread the
force of their power.
58
Currency (usually still exclusively metal), however,
began its metamorphosis into capital. In the interstices of dependent society,
traders do not accumulate their wealth just to flaunt it; they seek to
appreciate it through the expansion of their trading activities. It remains
that the profits derived from this appreciation are not directly associated to
job submission processes. The formula is A ! A ‘(A’ superior to A) passing through
exchange
E and not through capitalist
production P. The impression then is that exchange is productive (of profit),
as would say our neoclassical economists. This is only an impression. Because
the goods purchased by the trader to be sold elsewhere by him, are surely the
product of work – but the work of a craftsman or a peasant, not that of a
manual worker involved in a capitalist production process. Though – quite late
– early forms of it appear in the manufacturing
that precedes the machine in Asia and
later in Europe.
I have drawn attention here to two
facets of this issue:
(i)
that the transition from A ! E (exchange) ! A
‘to the formula A ! P (capitalist production) ! A’ represents a qualitative
leap, that involves
a transformation in social relations.
(ii) that
in the formula A ! E ! A ‘profit (commercial) is based on
comparisons of utility: silk is
popular with the rich user of fine clothes without him/her knowing where it
comes from, who produces it and how. Curiously, I said that the ‘value-utility’
that does not make sense in capitalism (it does not illuminate the reality, but
masks it) does in the old dependent/traders systems.
Once money becomes the means of work
of the trader, the invention of credit is imperative. The techniques of this
latter are already so richly developed long before capitalism. But with
capitalism credit, in turn, changes its nature.
8.
There is no thinkable capitalism without credit.
In the model of extensive
accumulation that I proposed and to which I refer to here (see among others its
mention in my book on the globalisation of value) I refer to my elaborations
(already old) on the issue of the realisation of profit that had plagued Rosa
Luxemburg. I think I had risen to the challenge and established that extensive
accumulation was possible on the condition that at the beginning of a
production period (one year, fifteen years, whatsoever) an advance is made to
the capitalist of an amount equal to the profit that he can make during this
period, allowing it to repay this advance at the end of the given period.
In this first sense, capitalism is still
financialised, and cannot be otherwise. But we must add that: the volume of
credit expansion necessary to enable extensive accumulation is calculable.
Neither much nor little. This requirement raises the serious question of credit
management, its issuance, the creation
59
and destruction of money through it. This
requirement is new, specific to capitalism, and does respond to questions
relating to credit in past noncapitalist trading systems.
9.
Credit management in capitalism raises a new issue: the credit must serve not
any capitalist (the borrower) but capitalism (the collective of capitalists)
since it must be determined in volume by the requirements of balance in
extensive accumulation.
Credit and State meet here in a
symbiotic relationship. The State, Engels reminded us, is not the defender of capitalists’ interests, but that ofcapitalism, and was then, in some cases,
against the interests of certain capitalists, sometimes many! The state at the
service of capitalists, or of some amongst them, is the corrupt State!
Similarly, credit must be managed by collective capitalism to
serve this latter, not capitalists, for their seemingly exclusive benefit.
Neoclassical economics, which cannot make this distinction, ignores the
question. Credit, for neoclassical economics, can be managed by its managers
(banks) on the exclusive basis of the profits that private capitalists and
individuals can gain from this management. To the real question: how much credit
is required by extensive accumulation? – it puts forward a false answer: the
price of liquidity.
Two sets of problems must be solved in the spirit of the
thesis I am elaborating here (which is none other than that of Marx, in my own
thinking).
The first concerns the nature of currency as a last resort.
Gold was the metal used for a long time during the earlier period of
capitalism. Marx proposed here immense developments on the relationship between
the volume of credit issued and the gold produced. His comments on the debate –
almost exclusively British in their time – between bullionists and advocates of
the bank, are, for this purpose, brilliant.
The abolition of convertibility – partial until 1971,
total since then – modifies the facts of the problem and the extent of options
for credit management. Credit has never been exclusively practiced for the sole
satisfaction of the requirements of extensive accumulation. There has always
been credit for private consumption (not very important before the contemporary
time) but especially a credit to the State. This is even way back before
capitalism. The old financialisations, highlighted by Giovanni Arrighi (The Long Twentieth Century, New Edition,
Verso, 2010) are of this nature; they rely on huge loans made by traders (or by
trading towns due to their glory) to monarchs.
In capitalism and with gold convertibility, the
possibility for the State to borrow from financial markets remains limited by
the requirements of convertibility. So it is therefore no coincidence that the
massive resort to these loans is rather that of peripheral states (the Ottoman
Empire, the Latin
60
American countries). The loan here is
guaranteed by the capitalist powers to be reimbursed through seizures in the
defaulting country via direct management of their taxation (especially
customs). Credit in this instance is simply a way of direct looting without
resorting to the establishment of forms of production that requires the direct
exploitation of labour. The indebtedness of contemporary Third World countries
and the structural adjustment policies that the global system imposed on them
are similar.
But once convertibility is abolished, the scope of
expansion of credit takes a quite different scale. In principle, the State can
borrow without limit from its central bank, which prints currency notes in
return. Of course, this action generates inflation, which reduces the cost of
reimbursement and imprisons in a vicious cycle that can be tragic. It is to
nullify this apocalyptic danger that Europe chose the extreme rules of the
Maastricht Treaty. And if the US has not been constrained to do as much today,
it is because the adoption of the dollar as international currency accepted by
the others allows the US debt transfer to others, forced to become her
creditors. But this is an issue we will meet later.
And in any event, even when convertibility is
abolished, gold remains present behind the scenes. All human societies to this
day need fetishes. In capitalism, it is gold. Here we discover another facet of
general alienation. The second set of questions concerns credit management:
private or public?
Banks, including central banks, have always been
private until World War I. This did not hinder much their operational
management as agents of capitalism as a whole. Because at that time, the
ownership of these banks (and they were plural) was distinct from that of
production companies that they were serving, even when, in Germany for example,
the rapport conglomerates/ banks was more marked than elsewhere. As a result,
banks were forced to obey the credit policies established by the central bank,
in close cooperation with the State.
François Morin (The
Wall of Money, Seuil 2006) has clearly demonstrated that this wall does not
separate a segment of capital (financial capital) from the other (productive
capital) but was built by capital as a whole to withstand the onslaught of its
victims, workers. Where, in given political conditions, the State is forced to
consider workers’ claims, the established wall then serves as an alibi to
facilitate its eventual betrayal of these workers and enable its return to its
normal function, of serving capital.
What has changed is not that financial capital would
be given a position to dominate productive capital, as our critical analysts
from the naive left would make us believe. Change is of a completely different
nature. In reaction to the crisis of 1970 to 1980, capital as a whole responded
through its increased
61
monopoly, to the point of arriving at the new
stage that I call the capitalism stage of generalized andfinancialised
oligopolies. By generalised, I mean that they now dominate the entire
‘productive’ apparatus of capitalism and no more segments of it, even when they
were important as was the case in the first capitalism of monopolies
(1890-1950). By financialised, I mean that oligopolistic groups bring together
production companies and financial institutions (banks, insurance companies,
pension funds, hedge funds, etc.). Therefore, it is no longer just financial
institutions that engage in financial markets operations, it is equally – and
on a great scale – companies known
as productive. This fact is known and
recognised by all, without our drawing necessary conclusions. The naive left
carries on as if it was an abuse that can be corrected while – as we shall see
later – contemporary capitalism can
be nothing else because there is no more
possible separation between financial institutions and companies known as
productive. François Morin gave a concise and magnificent presentation of this.
Under these conditions there is no more possible credit
policy, at the service of capitalism as a whole, but just a collection of
policies from each oligopolistic group on real production (relocation included)
and financing. Contemporary neoliberal economics welcomes this abolition of the
odious operations of the State in credit control. So what is to be done? The
fashionable thing today, in reaction to the severe financial crisis of September
2008, is to separate ‘good capitalism’
that is useful and effective, the type practiced by entrepreneurs who invest in
real production of goods and services and innovate in response to competition,
from the ‘bad capitalism’ of speculative financiers. From this distinction,
therefore, we propose regulations that should help, according to their authors,
in curbing the excessive financialisation of capitalism to favour the
restoration of healthy growth.
The most modest regulation proposals are limited to
lecturing and, in the best case, to limiting strictly, through regulations, the
huge salaries of traders and bankers, as proposed by Obama, Sarkozy, and
others.
Other projects, called ‘neo-Keynesian’ go much further.
These projects incorporate, into the array of regulatory measures designed to
limit speculation, a set of active policies designed to redistribute income in
favour of workers and to manage credit instruments, without hesitating in
anticipating the nationalisation of major banks and, maybe, even beyond. But
these projects remain in the logic of respect for private property, including
that of oligopolies that dominate the contemporary production system. I will
not recall here the criticism I made on all these projects which are, in my
view, illusory (see Appendix).
62
I will not hesitate to say that even the
nationalisation of all banks, insurance companies and other financial
institutions does not ensure the implementation of a credit policy other than
that required to perpetuate taxation of monopoly rents by the oligopolies. This
is so because of at least two major reasons. The first is that as long as these
oligopolies are not, in turn, nationalised, there is no reason to imagine that
they will not remain in charge, requiring nationalised banks to serve them
honestly. Now, the nationalisation of oligopolies is not on the agenda of
projects of the naive left. The second is that credit, at the service of
oligopolies, performs the inevitable function of support to the expansion of
Department III, the only possibility for running contemporary capitalism and
even of ensuring minimal growth. I will address this issue later.
10.
The confusion reaches its peak once we
confuse currency with creditmanagement.
Money is not a collective good but a very private
good. My money is not yours. And the management of an economic system even so
slightly decentralised, even in the early stages of socialist development,
demands it. The money of one business is not that of another!
The American Newspeak
has thrown here the greatest confusion on real stakes. We speak pointlessly
of these common goods that are
everything and nothing. But if money is a common
good, like atmospheric air (which is not a private property like money),
because it is a very useful good so why not say that food (beyond water!) and
many other things that are not less useful should not be subject to private
ownership? Advocating for full communism if we take thisNewspeak to heart. Why not? But it is certainly not for tomorrow,
much less not in the minds of its inventors!
The American Newspeak
offers a beautiful array of words deprived of real meaning such as
governance, civil society, whose contradictions I will not discuss here, so as
not miss our subject. This contemporary honest American English is not the
language of Shakespeare and Locke. It is a newspeak formatted to cloud minds
and bring in criticism that becomes very naive into the constraints of a
possible consensus, always liberal in the end, that is to say, pro-capitalist.
Many vague words authorize the exercise of apparent common sense to legitimise
different options. But common sense resists logical reason badly. We must break
free of this American slang and move away from it.
11.
Whenever there is currency and credit,
profit must be redistributed topay back loans. An interest rate on money
becomes necessary.
Here again, the interest of money had appeared before
capitalism, in the ranks of goods exchange. But it was frowned upon and
condemned by public opinion and often reserved for outcast minorities (albeit
wealthy), like
63
the Jews in Europe. But with capitalism,
interest rate becomes a means of implementing this credit policy designed to
ensure the volume of capital required in extensive accumulation, neither too
much nor too little.
We could have imagined another means of issuing and
distributing credit that could satisfy the requirements of accumulation without
interest payment : a (State) bank obeying the orders of Gosplan. This was more
or less the logic of the Soviet system for the distribution of funds between
companies.
The natural logic of capitalism, and respect for private
ownership of banks associated with it, would suggest the option of an interest
rate. This is watched by the central bank in order to match – more or less –
the volume of loans issued to the requirements of accumulation. I do mean more
or less since credit policies in question have never stopped the cycles and
have even shown amplitudes.
Neoclassical economics is required to give an explanation on
the rate of money (price of money) consistent with its whole language – to
everything its price, and fair price. The preference for cash, or the
depreciation of the future performs this function, especially as these concepts
refer to the homo economicus of all
times.
But reality, in turn, finds its reversed interpretation. It is
not shared profit that provides the interests on money. It is money that
becomes productive (as a factor of production) by itself. All that is
profitable is productive (by its profitability). The tautology is perfect.
Money makes money (while bypassing production). We are here confronted to
alienation to the power of 2, that I propose to call financial alienation to
distinguish it from general markets alienation, from which it comes,
nonetheless.
12.
Alienation continues on its path, and at each step reinforces the confusion
between so-called real economy and financialisation. Capitalist private
property concerns, in real terms, factories, offices, stores, service firms,
banks, etc. I will not discuss here the serious related problems that the exercise
of this property creates: ownership, possession, control, more or less
separated.
The key here is knowing that this property is the subject of
securities with legal status and value. And that these securities are in turn
goods that can be bought and sold. The price of these securities is based on
their estimated potential to produce profits. They are fluctuating, sometimes
volatile, always subject to potential speculation. It becomes impossible to
ignore that the value of a property is the subject of two parallel estimates:
in real terms, the value of plant equipment, the store’s stock, in financial
terms capitalisation
(at the interest rate!) of the profit
that its exploitation can bring. The fictitious capital represented by the
second form of assessment (if it can be called that) is not entirely separable
from the real evaluation, but it is well separated
64
from it in the real behaviours of the
buyers and sellers of these securities. If their imperative reconciliation does
not, automatically, take place at any point in time, crisis starts.
There is nothing really new here. Marx had already
made the comment in this sense on joint stock companies and operations in the
first stock exchanges in his time.
Accounting by capitalist enterprises is subjected to
different uses; either the reserves allocated to amortization are calculated on
real historical purchase price of the equipment in question or they are in
another way to take into account their depreciation when newer and more
efficient models are to replace them at a given period (accounting at market
prices). Europeans have generally given preference to the first method, the
North Americans to the second, which will become more widespread with
contemporary financialisation.
Marx (Capital,
Volume I, chap. VIII, page 233, TOK Edition, 2009) indeed considers capitalist
accounting at market prices, also perfectly consistent with the illusion
produced by alienation, that is the replacement of a virtual reality with a
real reality. The recourse of neoclassical economics to expectations shows the
formulation of this replacement.
The forms of these two accounting methods do not,
basically, give different results, but these forms produce impressions that
they are. Accounting at historical prices fuels the creation of reserves
corresponding to depreciations that are sufficient to ensure good assets
renewals. On the contrary, when these reserves are reduced to zero, the
estimated value of equipment in use becomes zero when new equipment is
available in the market, the writtenoff depreciation gives way to excess
profits of equal value. If this profit is distributed to shareholders, the firm
can only renew its equipment if its access to the financial market allows it.
The firm / market good side outweighs the firm / place of production side, as
is the case in contemporary capitalist economy, especially in the United
States.
13.
Financialisation is in no way an unfortunate drift and its explosion does not
extend to the loss of the growth of real economy of production. There is a good
dose of naivety in the proposals in the style of seriously-taken social
democracy that suggests the control of financial expansion and mobilisation of
financial surplus to support real growth. The tendency to stagnation is
inherent in capitalism of monopolies superbly analysed by Baran, Sweezy, and
Magdoff. Financialisation not only provides the only viable outlet to capital
surplus but remains the sole growth stimulus. Regressing financialisation
could, only, therefore weaken further growth of the real economy.
I refer here to the recent book by John Bellamy
Foster and Fred Magdoff (The Great
Financial Question, Monthly Review, 2009) that gives us the
65
best analysis of the contemporary stage of
financialisation. The volume of surplus generated in generalised oligopoly
capitalism minus the part of the surplus that oligopolies took for themselves
(their monopoly rent) are now such that the expansion of Department III needed
to absorb this surplus becomes impossible without a unlimited expansion of
credit in all its forms credit to consumers, credit to States. Herein lies the
secret of successive bubbles – that of computer technology, of property loans
(whose occurrence caused the 2008 financial crisis), that is in progress and
deals with raw materials and basic food products. Herein lies the secret of the
meteoric rise of sovereign debt, despite the prohibitions of the Maastricht
Treaty (for Europeans)
Policies have been consistently implemented to enable
this expansion, firstly the abandonment of the Bretton Woods (1971-1973) system
and the adoption of the generalised system of flexible exchange rates, imposed
by the IMF and proposed, in addition, to all countries of the periphery in the
new globalisation called neoliberal. The option in favour of these policies is
not the product of a drift inspired by dogmatic, even stupid monetarist theory.
There is no other option for truly existing capitalism. And it is in this sense
that capitalism is proving to be obsolete.
Foster and Magdoff show that the slow growth of Europe,
US, and Japan is accountable to the option of financialisation. The capitalism
of oligopolies is necessarily financialised ; its reproduction moves from
bubble to bubble.. A first bubble inevitably bursts when the pursuit of its
indefinite growth is hindered for any reason, and the system can only get out
of the financial crisis caused by the explosion by engaging in the manufacture
and swelling of a new bubble. Obviously, this form of accumulation weakens
global balance and the successive financial crises that follow in its path are
expected to produce in turn crises of the real economy. The probability that in
this truly existing capitalism, is regrouped the conditions of a balance of
real supply and demand (let alone those that match the imagination of markets
and the virtual economy associated with it), which allow an extensive
accumulation without problem, is almost zero.
That is why the crisis is a long system crisis and not a
financial crisis. I refer here (see appendix) to the analysis that I propose on
it that refuses the method based on the juxtaposition of crises – (financial,
energy, food,
ecological, etc.).
Could capitalism come out of this long crisis and indeed
emerge stronger. Fans of the illusion of capitalism-eternal-end-of-the story
are many who believe it. ‘Capitalism knows how to adjust to everything,’ they
will repeat.
In fact, if by capitalism they mean what
neoclassical economics says of it, their judgment is carved in stone. What
these fans cannot imagine is that if it
66
survives, capitalism will be forced
to deploy with even more violence the destructive dimensions of the capital
appreciation process that commands it.
To understand the reasons for the explosion of the
financial operations sector for thirty years, we should start analysing the
difficulties faced by capital accumulation.
But first it is necessary to remember that capitalist
accumulation is both real and financial and that the distinction between these
two sides of the same reality – truly existing capitalism – as useful as it
could be for the analysis of the contradictions of accumulation, should not
imply that the first of these faces would be positive and the second negative.
This is so because the real process and the financial process are complementary
and not at all competitors. Accumulation is as much of financial assets
accumulation as real assets. Foster and Magdoff (2009:68) write: ‘accumulation
is adding to the stock of existing capital goods... it is also adding to the
stock of existing financial assets’. The observation is important.
On these bases, Foster and Magdoff (2009:81, 106)
criticise the proposal from the famous Tobin tax precisely because it is based
on the assumption of competition rather than complementarity between real
investments and financial investments. Does it (i.e., adding to financial
assets) do so at the expense of producing real goods and services? And Foster
and Magdoff’s answer is in the negative. Tobin, like radicals in the United
States and elsewhere, are unaware that financialisation is functional for
capitalism.
Well-intentioned critics of the left of the American
radical schools do not understand it. Foster reminds us that, in their
writings, these critics speak continually of financial abuses that reduce the
possibilities of real accumulation. The claim is that the fall in financial
investment crowds out investment in the expansion and deepening of production
systems. This view by the European left and the majority of those who fall
under the banners of an alternate globalization is fundamentally and
consistently wrong.
Accumulation has always involved – at all
stages of the history of capitalism – real investments (equipment purchases),
credit expansion driven by the demands of balancing Departments I and II in
growth and simultaneously financial transactions of purchase and sale of
property titles.
In capitalism in its pre-monopoly stage
(roughly in the nineteenthcentury), the real dimension of accumulation is
expressed mainly – but never exclusively – by the requirements of balanced
growth divided among Departments I and
II and that of credit (which I have
called the active function of credit in accumulation).
This is no longer true in the capitalism of
monopolies (that is to say, since the end of the nineteenth century). As noted
above (see the first part),
67
accumulation now requires an expansion of
Department III. This requirement cannot be understood by neoclassical economics
and leads, therefore, to explanations unrelated to reality. Neoclassical
economics is incapable of understanding that monopoly capitalism is the product
of a persistent dominant tendency to stagnation. Analyses that involve
furthering the theory of value to rigorous empirical analysis, as Baran, Sweezy
and Magdoff, proposed for this purpose are no more read, or are misread.
Economists of our time deliberately ignore the analysis
of the fundamental contradiction of capitalism that leads to the recognition of
the persistent tendency of monopoly capitalism to stagnate. They suggest a
discourse on the cycle, the conditions of recessions and then successive
takeovers (from 1971 to today); as if the observation of the major fact that
growth rates since 1975 till date have always remained at levels that rarely
exceed half of what they were from 1945 to 1975 did not matter.
The assumption (erroneous) of conventional economics,
becomingdefining principles, is that strong growth is inherent to capitalism.
The observation of reality requires seeing things differently: it is strong
growth that is the exception and must be explained by special causes, the rule
being the tendency to stagnation. The thirty glorious years of strong growth
(1945-1975) are the exception. They come after the long crisis (1873-1945), of
which the last unfolding phase had produced two world wars and the two great revolutions
(1914-1945). The gigantic changes caused by these events are the cause of
international and social balances of power that are less unfavourable to the
peoples and working classes, who in turn are responsible for the exceptional
conditions of the accelerated growth of thirty glorious years. Then comes the
second long crisis that began in 1973 and from which we have by no means
emerged.
My presentation of this history of truly existing
capitalism of monopolies is different from that which links it to terms of long
cycles called Kondratieff. I will not repeat here the criticisms that I have
addressed to this last reading, based on the idea of a long-cycle downturn
caused by the internal logic of its deployment.
Department III is heterogeneous, I already said. But it
contains a significant financial component. It expands in parallel with the
expansion of Department III as a whole and even expands at a much faster pace.
Empirical evidence confirms it: the share of the financial sector in the
overall GDP is growing. This swelling is the product of the growing
difficulties of accumulation and not its cause. It is a form, among others, of
surplus absorption.
What I added to this analysis is the new stage of monopoly
capitalism, that I qualified as the stage of generalised oligopoly capitalism
(1970-1980), following the first form of monopoly capitalism (1880-1950/1970).
68
I proposed here the thesis that the fundamental
contradiction that characterizes accumulation is that which opposes production
capacity in strong growth to that of consumption in slower growth had reached
such a level of violence that the only possible solution for capital required
generalisation of the oligopolistic form of control of the economy. This is a
qualitative leap. Its consequence is that the growth of surplus (as defined by
Baran and Sweezy) accelerates and that the only possible answer then implies an
acceleration in the volume of financial transactions of which the proportion in
Department III is growing rapidly and violently. The flight of the volume from
these transactions that stand out now from that of the economy (Departments I,
II and III) is noted as from 1980.
To say that these operations are largely if not
entirely speculative and parasitic, or at the limit dishonest has absolutely no
bearing. Another capitalism is not possible, as Remy Herrera said. To say that
they replace the real investments that they hunt is wrong. Instead, Foster has
shown that the slow growth of economies of Europe, US, and Japan would have
still been much lower without this pumping up of the financier.
On the contrary, to say that this explosion
demonstrates that capitalism is an outdated system seems to me to be the
conclusion we must draw from it. But what is obsolete is not financial
capitalism but simply capitalism, that of oligopolies that can only be
financialised. Failing to be sufficiently radical, the criticism of radicals in
the US loses its radical nature. It becomes an expression of wishful thinking
and powerlessness, a moral sermon that Sarkozy, Obama or Stiglitz can safely
administer on us on behalf of capital.
The invention of means capable of offering financial
outlets to expanding surplus is not the cause of this expansion. It is rather
the consequence. We always invent what needs to be invented. The general logic
of these inventions, beyond their technical complexity, which forbids the right
people from understanding much of it is simple: overflowing insurances.
Ensuring profit (always uncertain), then ensuring this first insurance and so
on without end.
The swelling volume of financial accumulation – the
overflowing Insurance – among others involves limitless swelling of credit.
This is beyond the scope of the blueprint under which credit is the only active
agent of accumulation. Of course, let us mention it in passing: this swelling
would have been impossible in a monetary system that uses gold – to a second or
even tertiary degree. That is why the abandonment of Bretton Woods in 1971-1973
was demanded.
Indefinite swelling of credit responds to the concern
of liquidity in capital assets (real and financial) which now outweighs all
other considerations. We then understand that real assets themselves (physical
businesses, buildings, equipment, stocks of goods) must become as liquid as financial
assets.
69
Conventional economics does not explain the
reasons for this requirement. It replaces it with an ideological discourse
whose function is to give legitimacy to the reduction of physical assets to
forms of liquid assets.
We can say that the process is absurd. From the perspective of
social global rationality it is. But it is not from the standpoint of the
possessor of capital that uses them. And it is this rationality alone that the
system recognises. The nature of the conflict of these two rationales cannot be
grasped outside the analysis of alienation which drives the capitalist life.
I will make a probably daring, but hopefully
illustrative, parallel here. The fundamental alienation of the old systems was
metaphysical: it is God (in fact its definition by organized religion in the
society concerned) who makes history not men. We now understand that some
prelates (i.e., Catholics in the Middle Ages) may have been selling indulgences
or even square metres in paradise. And they have had buyers, victims of
dominant alienation at the time. Our ancestors were no less intelligent than
us. But their alienation was on other grounds. In capitalism it is now money
that makes history, an ordinary way of saying: that capital appreciation is at
the controls. We may then want to ensure a guarantee of the profit of the
fortune in question. Nothing very mysterious. A good form of security is also
the flight to tax havens. Paradise is perhaps not the term chosen here by
chance. The paradise of souls, far in heaven, is substituted with a paradise of
profit, down here.
To overcome a contradiction is not to resolve it. We overcome
a contradiction by remaining in the system that generates it. We solve it by
replacing this system with another which does not generate it.
In a beautiful article written in 2006 (cited: Chapter 3 of
the book by Foster and Magdoff ) the authors report the accelerated swelling of
FIRE (Finance, Insurance, Real Estate) needed to absorb the surplus. But beyond
that, they analyse it as being unsustainable; and leading yet to the production
of successive bubbles. And the bursting of a bubble (a financial crisis) finds
no solution (restoring financial trust) than feeding the preparation for
another. Because of the rigor of their analysis, the authors were among the few economists to predict the 2008
crisis.
14.
The transformation of capitalism into monopoly capitalism as the first form
(1890-1950) and then to generalised oligopoly capitalism (from 1970 to 1980)
resulted in a major systematic distortion of what is called the financial
market and a redistribution of the cards in the articulation of different
markets.
At all stages of its deployment, the dominant capitalist
market controls access to available capital, making it available to the
capitalists. In this first sense, financialisation is inherent in real capitalism
at all periods, it is not superimposed.
70
What has changed is who the capitalists who have
access to this market are (and therefore how this market is organised to
prioritise such access) and how these transformations reorganise any other
markets (production, labour markets, etc).
The grip of generalised oligopolies over the entire
capitalist system is expressed here by the almost total control of these
oligopolies on the financial and currency markets managed by banks and other
financial institutions that are stakeholders of groups that they constitute. In
common parlance, this means that only oligopolies access these markets. All
other potential borrowers are forced to go through them. Whether it is small
(the individual who applies for a mortgage or SMEs) or major (the States
themselves are caught in this trap for the investment of their bond, especially
the states of the South, of course). It is in this sense that I described the
financial market as the dominant market. For, indeed, the loans that
oligopolies get from this latter, which constitute the means of implementing
their expansion strategies in all areas (price competition, new product
launches, outsourcing and others), largely determine, at their turn,
configurations of downstream markets: product markets, markets from which
subaltern SMEs equip themselves, labour markets.
Of course neoclassical economics, which deliberately
ignores the realities of the world which it purports to report on, does not
pose such questions. It is merely satisfied with its theoretical thesis that
the level of employment is determined by wages and thus that full employment
requires that employees adjust their requests (actually accept lower wages) to
the required level to allow the profit rate that is acceptable to the
capitalists! The extended model of accumulation, to which I referred (notably
in my book on value), demonstrates the absurdity of this argument. The level of
employment is determined by the rate of accumulation and not vice versa.
Neoclassical economics also present a range of
financing options from which the capitalist chooses: the issue of shares or
bonds, borrowing. We deliberately ignore here that the capitalist in question
is concerned about retaining ownership (or at least control) of his business
and that this concern weighs decisively in his choices. At the time when the
French Ministry of Finance led econometric research that made sense, the
question was asked. I, in collaboration with a good mathematician (Nataf),
elaborated a model of price variables based on the (empirical) observation of
maximum foreign debt rate that these companies and major French groups of the
time could accept, in the absence of which their excesses would have threatened
their control. The model was very useful for highlighting state support
policies for industrial modernisation
71
15.
The generalised and financialised oligopoly capitalism is also globalised. The
scope of this globalisation is defined by the expansion requirements of these
oligopolies: opening to their export markets of the periphery (and to a lesser
extent that of the markets of the North to exports from the South), opening to
financial transfers, etc.
The opening is governed by the adoption – often imposed – of
the principle of flexible exchange rates. The advantages reaped, from this by
capital oligopolies in particular, and more generally Northern companies, are
considerable. The method allows a systematic undervaluation of peripheral
currencies that provokes distortions in the price system that favours the “consumers”
of the North and – equally important – further increasing the profits of
oligopolies that control international trade. The case of China, accused of
keeping the yuan undervalued to promote exports is not discussed here, if only
because China refuses full financial globalisation and maintains exchange rates
control. This method also allows raids through the invasion of peripheral
economies by available capital from the North, and then their abrupt withdrawal
after claiming super profits from speculation. The crises in Mexico, Argentina,
South, and South East Asia were largely the product of these raids. This
opening is further associated with the choice of the dollar as the quasi
exclusive international currency, maintained despite the financial shortcomings
of the United States.
The argument developed to make flexible exchange rates
acceptable, supposedly determined by the free and honest game of supply and
demand, is that of neoclassical economics: the market, globalised here produces
the best of worlds. It ensures the equilibrium of external balances, in
accordance with the doctrine of universal harmonies under the criticism that I
will not return to. Market alienation is the key that allows such flat,
ideological and dogmatic nonsense to be considered as scientific and to confuse
the requirements of dominant capital with what can be called inescapable
economic constraints. The real world consists of unequally developed nations
whose development requires the implementation of appropriate national policies
which cannot be substituted by a submission to the same general rule for all.
Who does not know that free trade still favours the most powerful, and
reproduces and deepens international inequalities?
Globalisation of the currency and financial market is
definitely the weakness of globalisation termed as neoliberal. No wonder that
it is through the rupture of this weak link that globalisation in place will be
called upon to implode, and that the countries of the South will re-invent
adequate forms of disconnection (un-globalisation), thus opening a new era of
awakening of Africa and the rest of the South.
No comments:
Post a Comment