Saturday, February 4, 2017

Development of Political Science as a Field of Study

10
The Development of Political Science as a Field of Study
The Greeks as we have seen established a broad definition of politics. However, between the sixteenth and early twentieth centuries, European political philosophers established a narrower definition of politics. For example, Jean Bodin (1430-1596), a French political philosopher, who first used the term “political science” (science politique) was a lawyer. Because of his legal training, Bodin focused on the characteristics of the state more than any other aspect of the political process. He concentrated on analyzing the relationship between the organization of the state and how this relates to law. Another French philosopher Montesquieu (1689-1755) argued that the functions of government could be encompassed within the categories of legislation, execution, and the adjudication of law.

Montesquieu categories found their way into the United States Constitution and other 119 Republican Constitutions with the assumption that liberty was best assured by separation of powers between the Legislature, the Executive and the Judiciary. It was the work of these two philosophers that imposed a restricted definition of politics on political scientists. Political scientist for years concentrated almost exclusively on the Executive, the Legislature and the Judiciary as major concern until recently. In the mid-nineteenth century, Darwin’s theory of evolution and natural selection began to exert a powerful influence upon political science. In fact, Biology came to reinforce history in the study of political institutions, which were seen as the product of historical change and, apparently organic evolution.

The development of sociology after the 19th century prompted political scientists to give more attention to the impact on government of social forces not defined with reference to the institutional outline of the state. The industrialization of previously agricultural societies and sharpening clash between the emergent working classes and their employers (industrialists) compelled a closer study of economic facts, forces and trends, as these produced political problems and helped to shape political behaviour.

The advent of World War II brought about a re-think by political scientist that Legislature, Executives, agencies, and the Courts did not exist by themselves and that they did not operate independently of one another or of the other political organizations in society. Political scientists in America and Europe embarked on new fields of study by examining the political parties, interest groups, trade unions, as well as corporations and church organizations. Ideologies have also commanded the attention of political scientists because of their (ideologies) role in the formation of Ultra-Right and Ultra-Left political parties and movements.

It is all the above institutions of the state plus other political and social organization that constitute the political system. What this mean is that politics is not just about government and politicians but a complex process involving everybody in a given society, attitudes to issues, interest groups, group organization, electioneering, as well as the formulation, implementation, and interpretation of law. SELF-ASSESSMENT EXERCISE 1 Define politics and describe the development of political science as a field of study.

CODE: 22

Introduction to Political Science

9
Definitions/Explanations of Politics

Generally speaking, it is difficult to define politics because there are many definitions by various scholars that conflict or sometimes complement one another. Ernest Baker (1962:1) stated that politics is the process of making and execution of governmental decisions or policies. Harold Lesswell and Abraham Kaplan (1950) defined politics as authoritative, allocation of values or who gets what, when and how. Austine Ranany (1975: 35-38) maintained that politics is a process of resolution of conflict in society. For Max Weber, (1947:145-154) politics is the operation of the state and its institutions. Politics for him, means the sharing power to influence the distribution of power among individuals and groups within a state.

Lasswell suggests that politics is essentially the struggle for positions of power and influence by which those who succeed in monopolizing such positions in society are able to make decisions that affect the lives of every citizen within the country. More will be said about power later when we examine it as a topic on its own. For our purpose, politics can simply be defined in three ways: First, it attempts to discover the general principles, formation and functioning of government. Secondly, it is concerned with people and the way in which they make decisions and the way those decisions are reached. Thirdly 118 politics is that part of the social sciences which treats the foundations of the state and the principle of government, governmental, social and economic programmes, international relations, organizations and cooperation. Politics goes beyond the activity of government, the political parties and the politicians.


Politics is a universal phenomenon- that is, it is present in all human organization such as the family, trade unions, corporations, universities, etc. In all these organizations, politics is characterized by struggle for power and influence, conflict, bargaining, reconciliation, resolution and consensus. Politics can be played at a national level or internationally. At the national level, the failure of the Nigerian political elite between 1962-66 gave the military the opportunity to intervene in our political process. History repeated itself in 1983 when the political elite again failed to settle their differences following the 1983 October general elections. Again, the military employing their monopoly over the use of force and the acquiescence of the Nigerian people swept the political elite off the political stage and ruled until 1999. Similarly, it was politics at the international level when the Palestinian and the Israelites partly resolved their age-long military/ideological confrontation over Palestinian home land in Gaza. Also it was a political action/decision when ECOMOG troops were sent by West African States to war-torn Liberia for peace-keeping operations. This helped to stop the fighting from getting worse. Peace has now returned to Liberia after 15 years of fighting.


CODE: 88

Nature and Scope of Political Science

8
THE NATURE AND SCOPE OF POLITICAL SCIENCE CONTENTS
1.0 Introduction
2.0 Objectives
3.0 Main Content
3.1 Definitions/Explanations of Politics
3.2 The Development of Political Science as a Field of Study
3.3 What is Science? What makes Political Science a Science?
3.4 The Meaning of Verifiability
3.5 The Meaning of Systematic
3.6 The Meaning of Generality or Universality

1.0 INTRODUCTION In this unit, you will be introduced to what Politics is all about.
In your day to day activities, you must have heard of the word Politics without actually understanding its meaning. What do you think is Politics? This question has been asked many times in every age before the birth of Jesus Christ – when the Greeks first introduced the idea of the ‘polis’ meaning city-state. It is from ‘polis’ that we derive our modern word politics. Aristotle (384-322 BC) in his book POLITICS first used the term politics to refer to the affairs of a Greek city-state. Aristotle observed that ‘man by nature is a political animal’. By this he meant that the essence of social existence is politics and that two or more men interacting with one another are invariably involved in a political relationship. Aristotle observed that whenever men seek to define their position in society or as they attempt to achieve personal security from available resources and as they try to influence others to accept their points of 117 view, they find themselves engaged in politics. In this broad sense, every one is a politician.

Today, the word politics is an elastic one. To some authorities, politics is concerned with the ordinary day-to-day activities of the community in which we are all personally involved. To others, including Harold Lasswell, politics has been equated with the study of power or the study of influence and the influential. In fact, Lasswel went as far as to define politics as “who gets what, when how” which underlines the importance of power as the major ingredient of politics.
2.0 OBJECTIVES At the end of this unit, you should be able to:
· explain what politics is all about

· explain the development of political science as a subject of study and why political science is regarded as a science.


CODE: GG

Is Political Science Really a Science?

7
What is Science? What Makes Political Science a Science?
Pure science is concerned with obtaining accurate knowledge about the structure and behaviour of the physical universe. It deals with universal and with rational analysis of known facts. It is fact seeking as well as fact-using. The ultimate goal of a science is the classification of facts, and on the basis of such classification, the formulation of a body of general rules and logically consistent and universally valid statement about the universe. Science has been described as an “adventure of the human spirit”. The scientific method entails vigorous procedures starting from selection of problems to be solved or analysed, followed by formulation of hypothesis, gathering of data and testing of hypothesis, and finally, the use of findings to refute, modify or support existing theories.

To evaluate the findings of their own studies and of others, scientists employ a number of knowledge, to be scientific it must be characterized by verifiability; it must be systematic and must, have general applicability.

3.4 The Meaning of Verifiability
A proposition is said to be verified when it has been checked or tested by many specialists in the relevant field of study and when they all agree that other scientists and the general public can believe it to be true. However, there are no certainties in anything but probabilities. The probability that some propositions will hold true, is so great that they can be treated as certainties, but in the social sciences, this is not the case. If scientific knowledge is to be verifiable, science must be empirical, that is, scientific statements must be descriptive of the empirical world. Similarly, if scientific knowledge is to be verifiable, the desire for reliability and, ultimately, for verifiability has been the chief factor leading to the adoption of quantitative methods.

3.5 The Meaning of Systematic
Knowledge is said to be systematic when it is organized into an intelligible pattern, or structure, with significant relationships made clear. To achieve a system, scientists seek out similarities and differences putting things together. While looking for similarities and differences, scientists also look for relationship, whether correlations or causal relations. Concern for system means that scientists want to proceed from particular towards general facts, from knowledge of 121 isolated facts towards knowledge of connections between facts. Thus, “the ideal of science is to achieve a systematic inter-connection of facts”.

3.6 The Meaning of Generality or Universality
The knowledge provided by a telephone directory anywhere in the world is verifiable, and it is presented in an orderly and systematic way. However, it lacks generality or universality in the sense that a New York Telephone Directory is useless in the City of Lagos. The object in science is to develop generalizations so that explanation and prediction can occur to the maximum possible extent. Scientific knowledge on any subject, designed to facilitate explanation and prediction can be thought of as a pyramid rising from a base of specific bits of data up through more general facts to propositions, laws, and theories. Turning to the second part of our questions: Is political science really scientific? Political science may be defined as the study of politics using some scientific tools. Political science is not and cannot be an exact science in the sense of the natural sciences like physics, chemistry, geology, etc. The reasons for this are that the subject matter which political scientists investigate is generally uncertain in forms – that is, people are generally unpredictable. Thus, the conclusions reached after investigations are dubious and the findings are not all of general or universal applicability.

Political science is not an exact science like the natural sciences because the material with which it deals is incapable of being treated exactly the same way as physics or chemistry. While physics and chemistry are natural or physical science, and deal with matter; the social sciences which include political science, sociology, economics, etc. deal with man in society. Man in society is not only unpredictable but also extremely cumbersome to observe accurately because he is ever-changing and his environment is difficult to control. Political science like other social sciences has a scientific character because of the scientific method it employ in examining phenomena. That is, it is a science to the extent that it accumulates facts that are verifiable, links these facts together in causal sequences (systematically) and from these, makes generalizations of fundamental principles and formulate theories.

The laboratory method of the natural science may be difficult for political scientists to adopt but they could observe historical facts and the facts of contemporary world as the basis for political analysis, 122 classify, connect and compare. However, political scientists do not agree on the appropriate categories for classifying the phenomena of politics. This disagreement reflects the difficulty of observing and the frequent impossibility of quantifying the variables that political scientists identify. Finally, because political scientists deal with large numbers of people in an uncontrolled setting where each individual has many behavioural options open to him, it is near impossible to make generalization on observed facts. The most crucial fact is how one defines, much less measure, political power and influence the very substance of the political process. Our assessment of political power will be highlighted when we examine power, authority and influence in another unit.

SELF-ASSESSMENT EXERCISE 2 Is Political Science a science or an art subject?

4.0 CONCLUSION The development of Political science as a discipline shows its attempt in enhancing its scientific status. We are however informed that political science is not and cannot be an exact science in the sense of the natural sciences like physics, chemistry, geology, etc. The reasons for this are uncertainty and unpredictability of the subject matter which political scientists investigate.

5.0 SUMMARY In this unit, you have been exposed to what politics is about; the development of political science as a distinct field of study and its scientific status. We tried here to show you that although there is no universally acceptable definition of the word “politics”, however, there are some working definitions that will guide you as new “entrants” in the field.

6.0 TUTOR-MARKED ASSIGNMENT
i. Discuss what you understand by the term politics.
ii. Describe the development of political science over the years.

iii. Why are the natural sciences more ‘scientific’ than political science? 

CODE: 55

Basic Concepts and Theories in Political Science

7
Keywords: basic concepts in political science
Basic Concepts / Theories

            The Political System is made of three (3) important parts:
                        a) The Political Regime
                        b) The Political Personnel
                        c) The Political Community

The Regime - is the structure of the institutional configuration of government e.g., in U. S. we have three branches of government and different levels of government e.g., federal, state, and local.

The Political Personnel - are the people in government at any particular time or place e.g., Richard Nixon was the political personnel in the office of the Presidency during 1969 - 1974.

The distinction between the regime and personnel can be seen in the change that occurred with the following:

            President Richard Nixon in USA
            Adolph Hitler in Pre WWII Germany

            In the U. S. Nixon resigned as President but the office of the Presidency continued,
            we changed personnel but not regime.

In Germany there was no change in personnel but there was an important change in regime.  Germany went from a democracy to an authoritarian and then a totalitarian regime under Adolph Hitler’s leadership.

The Political Community are all those affected by government.

There are three (3) models of how the political process works within the political regime.

            1) Elitism
            2) Participatory Democracy
            3) Pluralism









 http://www.kean.edu/~ckelly/basicconcepts.doc



Elitism maintains society is hierarchically organized with a few deciding and the many following.  Elitism makes no claim of being democratic.

There are two (2) variations of elitism:

1) One school of thought maintains that elitism is natural and can be beneficial for society
                e.g., Plato’s Republic wise philosopher-kings will rule for the betterment of society.

            2) Another school of thought maintains that elitism is inevitable to do human nature,
bureaucracy, or the economic system.  This school maintains that elitism is an exploitative type
of system, where the rulers exploit the ruled e.g., Marx maintain that in Feudalism and Capitalism the rulers ruled in their own interest at the expense  of the many.  (See Chart I)

Participatory Democracy maintains that in order for the political system to be truly democratic, society has to be democratized, i.e., all structure in society, family, job, church, etc. have to abandon their hierarchical structure and become democratic.

In order to appreciate what the proponents of participatory democracy are saying it is useful to view democracy on a continuum ranging from pure totalitarianism to pure democracy.

ABSOLUTE                                      Reality                                    ABSOLUTE
Totalitarianism------------------------------------------------------------Pure Democracy
e.g. George Orwell’s             Somewhere in between                      Equal Influence
          1984                                                                                                 for all

Proponents of Participatory Democracy wants to break down the hierarchical structure and move toward collective decision-making where the many are deciding their own fate.  Some proponents of Participatory Democracy concede that it is impractical to achieve absolute equality of influence but nonetheless that should be the goal of society e.g. Marx’s Communist Utopia.

Pluralism maintains that the political system is hierarchically structured, i.e., there are a few deciding and many follows.  Despite this fact, pluralism maintains democracy is possible, i.e., the many can make the few responsive, accountable and accessible.  The way this is done is as follows:

            1) No one group in society has a monopoly of power.
            2) In order to make governmental policy coalitions of groups have to be formed and
                groups in society are pragmatic enough to work out compromises.
            3) There is a basic consensus w/n society that rules out violence as a legitimate
                 way to resolve group conflict.
                        a) this consensus also involves a widespread agreement on a mechanism for
                            making decisions.,
                        b) this mechanism is considered legitimate i.e., the losers are willing to comply
                            with the decision of the winners.
                        c) another requirement is that the winners permit the losers to criticize and
                            challenge the winners’ decision.     See figure-1, Pluralism.gif
































A Pluralist democracy is characterized by competition by power by organized groups.  The unorganized have little or no power in the political system.

Political Regime - regardless of the type of regime all regimes seek legitimacy.  Legitimacy is the tacit or explicit support of the regime by its people.  Usually it is an emotional identification with the regime.  The regime is legitimate when the people believe that institutional structures of the government are the most appropriate for society.

There are various sources of legitimacy.  Max Weber speaks of three (3) ideal types of legitimacy:

            1) Traditional - people support the regime out of habit and custom.
            2) Rational legal - people support the regime because the explicit rules and procedures of
                government make sense to the people--the people prefer on rational grounds the rule
                of law over other types of rule.
            3) Charismatic - people support the regime because of an emotional identification with the
                personality of the leader of the regime.

According to Weber we find mixes of the three (3) types of legitimacy in every society but it is possible to categorize regime by the dominant source of legitimacy.  (See Chart II)



Political Culture - In order to understand legitimacy it is important to comprehend the political culture of society.

Political culture is the values, beliefs, attitudes and aspirations of the people in society which orient them politically.  In order for a regime to be legitimate there has to be widespread agreement in society on certain sets of values i.e., some sort of a consensus.

Ideology is an explicit set of values that orients people in society in terms of what they can expect from government and what government should do for them and society.  It speaks to human nature, the role of government in society and the relationship of politics and economics.  It also advances the economic interests of a social class in society.

The three (3) main ideologies of politics are Conservatism, Liberalism and socialism.  There are many variations of the ideologies i.e., fascism, Nazism, communism, populism, etc., but they all can be traced back to one or more of three.  (See Chart III)







POLITICAL SCIENCE
LECTURE NOTES                                                                          DR. CHARLES KELLY




CHART I

MARX’S THEORY OF HISTORY – ECONOMIC DETERMINISM


Stages of
History


Environment  

Societal
Relationships
Territorial
Political Units
Classes
Source of
Legitimacy
Economic
System
Primitive
Communism


Abundance
Harmony
None
None
None
None
Feudalism



Scarcity
Conflict
City-state
Noble vs.
Peasants
Religion
Agrarian
Capitalism



Less
Scarcity
Conflict
Nation-state
Bourgeoisie
      vs.
Proletariat
Nationalism
Industrial
Socialism



Least
Scarcity
Conflict
Regional
Camps
Proletariat
     vs.
Bourgeoisie
Working-class
Consciousness
Highly
Industrialized
Communism



Sufficiency
Harmony
Global
Society
None
Equality
Nearly
Automated
















CHART II

WEBER’S TYPOLOGY OF DIFFERENT POLITICAL REGIMES

(THE TYPE OF REGIME LEGITIMACY INFLUENCES POLITICAL STABILITY)


TYPES OF LEGITIMACY
PROBLEM I

Dealing with Transfer of
Power
PROBLEM II

Dealing with the Pheno-
menon of Change
POLITICAL STABILITY

(Dealing with Problems
 I & II)


CHARISMATIC

(Regime accepted by the
  People because of the
 personality of its leader)

Deals Poorly

(Cannot Transfer
  Personality of Leader)

Deals Well

(Can Muster Necessary
   Political will

Less Stable




TRADITIONAL

(Regime accepted because
 it based on tradition and
 custom)
Deals Well

(e.g., law of primogeniture)
Deals Poorly

(Can not break   with
  Tradition
   
Less Stable






RATIONAL - LEGAL

(Regime accepted because
  procedures are perceived
 logical and reasonable)

Deals Well

(Elections, explicit line of
 succession)



Deals Well

(Legislation, Amendments
 and judicial review)
Most Stable






























CHART III

MAJOR IDEOLOGIES


                         Class                 Historical               Economic                Role of                  Nature of               Source of
                                Constituency        Origins                   System                   Government         Man                       Power                 

Conservatism




Nobility
18th Century
Mercantilism
Paternalistic
(Strong
 Government)
Anti-Social

Land

Liberalism




Middle Class
19th Century
Capitalism
Laissez Faire
(Weak Government)

Social

Commerce

Socialism
Working Class
20th Century
Centrally Owned and
Planned Economy
Interventionist (Strong
Government

Malleable

Numbers &
Organizations










Dr. Charles P. Kelly


----- End -----


CODE: 11

Development of World Civilizations

6
Development of Various Civilizations in the World
Keyword: development civilizations world
Iqbal U* History Programme, Faculty of Social Sciences and Humanities, National University of Malaysia, Malaysia *Corresponding author: Iqbal U, History Programme, Faculty of Social Sciences and Humanities, National University of Malaysia, UKM 43650, Bangi Selangor, Malaysia, Tel: 60389215555; E-mail: uqbah@siswa.ukm.edu.my Copyright: © 2016 Iqbal U. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. Citation: Iqbal U (2016)
Development of Various Civilizations in the World. Arts Social Sci J 7: e107. doi:10.4172/2151-6200.1000e107
The Arts and Social Sciences Journal is an international peerreviewed open access journal that publishes articles related to the latest developments in the field culture, literature, arts and other areas of social sciences. The current vol 7 issue 2 published 15 research articles, seven opinion articles, two review articles and a short commentary.

In the research article Bayeh assessed the principles agreed between Egypt, Ethiopia and Sudan UeaٹUming the past colonial agreements on the Nile [1]. Furlan’s article investigated about the spatial form of West Bay’s contemporary built environment which consolidates the cultural identity, contributing to the image of Doha as a modern city [2]. Godana described the role of indigenous knowledge of Borana pastoralists in managing their rangelands [3]. Furlan et al. studied about the architecture of Italian Trans-national houses built in Brisbane and concluded that the architecture is influenced by the need for continuing architectural and cultural traditions in the host country. The\ supposed that the spatial distribution of the artifacts was influenced by socio-cultural factors of both the native and hosting built environment [4].

Hossain analyzed the influence of Henrik on the social drama, God of Rachel Crothers and Susan, on social themes and moral problems aوٴecting women, especially in sexual double standard, free love, trial marriage, divorce and prostitution [5]. Al-Asadi and Al-Zubaidy explored the influence of Al-Jazeera news and U.S. news in shaping the perspectives of United States population towards the Middle East [6]. Klapisch-Cohen and Bartuv described about the body psychotherapy supervision especially the relationships between therapy and supervision and the resonance through the body [7]. Sarsenovaa et al. assessed the professional capacity of the young people and their professional potential of an expert associated with employment in the Republic of Kazakhstan [8]. Hassen described the role of talk plays in the Kung society of South West Africa [9]. Guruge et al. analyzed the intimate partner violence (IPV) women worldwide as a major health concern [10].

Mukuni et al. evaluated the social motivations in Kiritiri open-air miraa (khat) market people of Mbeere South, which is a sub-county within Embu County related to use of swearwords among miraa (language) traders [11]. Mohammed assessed the major causes and consequences of cross border illegal migration of people from rural areas of one country to urban areas of the other countries, especially the Gulf nations [12].


Hasen assessed the attributes of manzuma on Wollo Muslim community [13]. Iqbal wrote his opinion on British Policy towards the Singapore-Malaysia Relations and in another article he described about Hamas Struggle. Iqbal in his article bUiefl\ discussed about the Malaysia and Japan Relations and in another article he described about

CODE: 66

Criminalising Communism: Trans National Politics in Europe

5
Criminalizing Communism: Transnational in Europe
Keywords: criminalizing communism transnational politics europe
Maria Mälksoo
DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/ips.12041 82-99 First published online: 1 March 2014
ArticleInformation & metricsExplore
PDF
Abstract
The Eastern enlargement of the European Union has intensified calls for the reconstruction of a common European remembrance of the continent's multiple totalitarian legacies. Various political initiatives to condemn, along with counter-attempts to re-legitimize, the legacy of communism have emerged at the pan-European level. Each aspires to leave an imprint on the symbolic moral order and the legal regime of the broader European community. This article builds a conceptual framework for understanding the contestation of political and juridical regulation of the transnational remembrance of totalitarian communist regimes in Europe. Critically engaging the concept of cosmopolitanization of memory, it is argued that mnemonic identity in Europe is being transformed via new claims on “European memory.” These claims are being made by various East European actors seeking recognition of the region's particular historical legacies as part of the pan-European normative verdict on twentieth-century totalitarianisms.
In December 2010, the European Commission rejected calls made by six East European countries to criminalize the denial of crimes perpetrated by communist regimes, in the same way as a number of EU countries have banned the public condoning, denial, and gross trivialization of the Holocaust. The EU Council Framework Decision (2008) on combating racism and xenophobia does not cover crimes directed against a group of persons defined by reference to criteria other than race, color, religion, descent, or national or ethnic origin—such as social status or political convictions, for example. As the denial of crimes committed by totalitarian communist regimes is likewise largely absent in the national legislation of EU member states (with the exception of the Czech Republic, Poland, Hungary, Lithuania, and, somewhat less explicitly, Latvia), the Commission concluded that the necessary legal conditions for adopting an additional legislative instrument for tackling these crimes at EU level had not yet been met (European Commission 2010). As is often the case, the legal justification hides further political controversies: many suspect the undertaking to include international crimes against social and political groups (which comprise the bulk of so-called communist crimes) into the European Union's area of legal coverage to be a thinly veiled attempt to mitigate East Europeans' own complicity in the Holocaust (Guerreiro in European Parliament 2009c; Katz 2009). Seeking equal legal treatment of totalitarian crimes of different origin is thus regarded as political relativism, threatening to “dilute the unique nature of the Nazi crimes” (Ford in European Parliament 2009c).

Recent years have indeed witnessed intensified attempts on the part of various East European actors to politically condemn and criminalize the totalitarian communist legacy by means of national, European, and/or international law. At a pan-European level, this has resulted in a sequence of political declarations, legal initiatives, and resolutions by the Council of Europe (CoE), the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR), the Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe (OSCE), and the European Union, condemning totalitarian communist regimes in various ways. As the debates held in these multiple political fora demonstrate, efforts to influence the normative and institutional formation of a pan-European remembrance of communist regimes have hardly gone unchallenged. The meaning of the communist legacy for the “European memory” has emerged as a political issue of substantial controversy and significance. How, then, should we make sense of this struggle over criminalizing totalitarian communist regimes in Europe? On what basis is the institutionalization of the “memory” of totalitarian communism being called for? And what discourses are invoked in the respective pan-European mnemopolitical debates?

Exploring how initiatives to condemn totalitarian communist regimes are translated into the symbolic moral order and legal regime of the broader European community brings to the fore an overlooked aspect of transnational mnemopolitics in Europe. It is not that existing research has ignored the normative power of constructing a “common European memory”—indeed, it has paid considerable attention to it (Spohn and Eder 2005; Challand 2009; Jarausch 2010; Karlsson 2010; Leggewie 2010; Pakier and Stråth 2010; Littoz-Monnet 2012). Rather, current works have largely failed to theorize the normative implications of mounting calls for the juridification of “remembering” communism for the dynamics of transnational mnemopolitics in Europe, nor have they adequately captured the role of East European actors in the process (cf. Closa 2010a,b, 2011). While there is a growing acknowledgment of the transformation and pluralization of European memory regimes in the literature (Levy and Sznaider 2007:174), the diversification of the mnemonic inventory in Europe remains to be substantiated, with analyses focusing on the new trajectories of remembrance intersecting with the established mnemonic code of the Holocaust.

This article develops a conceptual framework in order to begin to fill this void. Taking account of the various calls to criminalize, and counter-attempts to re-legitimize, the legacy of totalitarian communist regimes in Europe, I sketch out a condensed genealogy of the formation of a common assessment, or “memory,” as it is often dubbed, of the communist legacy at four main pan-European fora, paying particular attention to the increasing volume of juridifying discourses. A genealogy—what Nietzsche (1967) conceived as “effective history” (wirkliche Historie) and Foucault (1984) as a “history of the present”—aims to describe how the present became logically possible (Bartelson 1995:7), or to illuminate a contemporary phenomenon that is deemed to be problematic from the perspective of the past (Elbe 2001:260–263). As a Foucaultian genealogical approach is specifically concerned with interpreting the sources of moral discourses (Price 1995:85–86), and demonstrating the diversity and specificity of battles between different interpretations of social phenomena (Vucetic 2011:1301), it is particularly well suited for explaining the scattered emergence of a pan-European discourse of remembering communism. A genealogical inquiry into pertinent debates from the CoE and the ECtHR to the OSCE and the European Union highlights how something is reclaimed from the past—in this case the communist legacy—for the purpose of reinvigorating a particular understanding of “common European values” in the present or, indeed, questioning “the value of these values themselves” (see Nietzsche 1967:20). Legal debates disclose the attempted translation of specific national and regional experiences into pan-European norms and practices, providing a window into understanding law as a medium of collective remembrance, aimed at furnishing a particular sense of European community (cf. Levy and Sznaider 2010:18). Embracing four pan-European fora enables us to examine areas of overlap and the mutual reinforcement of tropes of condemnation across distinct organizations, illuminating recognition-seeking and struggles for mnemonical hegemony, contingency, and resistance in the operation of the emerging moral discourse. Zooming out of the European Union is therefore essential for incorporating the respective pan-European debates with the active presence of the representatives of the Russian Federation as political and legal successor to much of the communist experiment in Europe (cf. Rostoks 2011). This approach tallies with the so-called three E definition of genealogy—a reference to episodes, examples, and effectiveness in bringing about a particular normative assessment of the past in the context of the present (Vucetic 2011:1300). The empirical account offered here is necessarily episodical; exploring a more comprehensive evolution of the discourse on the remembrance of communism through a condemnatory prism would have necessitated a considerably broader focus, with a wider range of discursive genres and fora, starting at least with the critical debates related to the publication of The Black Book of Communism in France in 1997 (1999 in English) and the German Historikestreit in the late 1980s.

I propose two non-exclusive contexts through which debates over the pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes may be theorized. First, the way in which East European actors of various stripes have taken the so-called Holocaust template and modeled their own quest for determining the contents of the “European memory” accordingly warrants a critical interrogation of the concept of the “cosmopolitanization of memory,” underpinned by the remembrance of the Holocaust as the universal ethical problem (Levy and Sznaider 2010). As a mnemonic signifier, the Holocaust is an example of the transnational memory discourse, putting pressure on national narratives and thereby reshaping them (Berger 2012:31). If communism was supposed to “embody, exemplify and spread a kind of universal, therefore universally comprehensible, culture” (Judt and Snyder 2012:239), this article seeks to fathom whether a universalist ethos of a similar kind is informing the contemporary anti-communist movement in Europe. I maintain that the pan-Europeanization pursuits of the mostly East European recollections of communism offer an intriguing case of transnational remembrance in the making. Lessons drawn from the Second World War (WWII) and the Nazi atrocities once laid the foundation for the European project, making it “a peculiar kind of monument to the Second World War” (Müller 2010:30), with Holocaust recognition as a “contemporary European entry ticket” (Judt 2010:803). The campaign for the pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes calls inter alia for the revision and substantive enlargement of the existing constitutive narrative of the European Union, raising potentially uncomfortable questions for some about West European complicity with the East European postwar plight under communist rule. The remembrance of WWII and the communist legacy are thus closely connected in Europe, given the very centrality of WWII as the founding event of the European project.

Second, I suggest that the East European politics of seeking pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes in explicitly universalist, moral, and increasingly legal terms is an evocative example of the expression of political grievances over insufficient recognition of the region's particular historical legacies. Seeking condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes and, furthermore, the criminalization of the denial of crimes committed by these regimes at the pan-European level, interrogates, in particular, the hegemonic mnemonic narrative of the pre-Eastern enlargement European Union with its exclusive denouncement of the Holocaust. As the debates in multiple pan-European fora demonstrate, the struggle for the universal condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes is a sub-strand of the human rights movement which strives to expand the official pan-European category of criminal totalitarianism. This endeavor (which in fact reaches back to the very origins of the Cold War) is based on an assumption of the universal dignity of all victims, regardless of the perpetrator regime. It stems from a position of ethical cosmopolitanism, maintaining that a shared sense of European-ness should make the historical injustices caused by totalitarian communist regimes a universal concern for all Europeans.

The politics of recognition comprises, particularly at EU level, attempts to broaden the base of the “universal lessons” of totalitarianism in Europe in order to turn the particular East European experiences with totalitarian communist regimes into a part of the established European mnemonic “master narrative.” This is exemplified by the predominantly East European membership of the all-party Reconciliation of European Histories Group in the European Parliament, chaired by the Latvian representative, Sandra Kalniete, and aimed at “including the experience of the postcommunist nations into common narrative of the European History.” The numerical preponderance and vocality of East European interventions in debates at Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe (PACE) and the European Union reflects further this struggle for recognition (see Rostoks 2011:196–197 for a detailed account). Important public hearings and international conferences on the subject of crimes committed by totalitarian regimes have been organized under the aegis of the Slovenian, Czech, Hungarian, and Polish EU Presidencies in 2008–2011. Calls for the pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes explicate a move from the renationalization of memories (typical during the immediate aftermath of communism in Eastern Europe) to postnationalist aspirations. These initiatives also constitute a demand for political justice of a particular kind. By seeking recognition for the inclusion of their encounters with communism into the established European mnemonical narrative of twentieth-century totalitarianisms, the East European mnemonic actors concurrently seek recognition for their agency as Europeans (Mälksoo 2009).

While the experiences and assessment of communism in Eastern Europe have hardly been homogeneous (Judt 2010), this politics of recognition is also designed to legitimate a particular regime of truth in the countries making the pertinent claims. It is therefore important to identify that although the fault lines of “European memory” along the Cold War East–West dichotomy are regularly emphasized in debates, mnemonical unity is nonetheless illusory on both sides. The alleged anti-communist consensus varies greatly in the postcommunist countries of Eastern Europe (Troebst 2010). Likewise, the discourse of the various spokespersons seeking to condemn totalitarian communist regimes frequently obfuscates the distinctly heterogeneous views among so-called Western public opinion on the issue, breaking down the binary between fiercely anti-communist “East” and indifferent “West.” While no tidy symmetry exists between different assessments of the communist legacy in the East and West of Europe, it is nonetheless undeniable that before the Eastern enlargement of the European Union, the institutionalized European remembrance remained largely silent on the issue.

The current shift toward adopting a condemnatory stance toward the communist legacy owes much to the interpretation of European values and identity, as opposed to the tenets of totalitarianism. This sentiment was evocatively captured by a Czech politician, Alexander Vondra, as President-in-Office of the Council of the European Union during the European Parliament debate on European Conscience and Totalitarianism. He claimed that the European Union:
… stands for everything that is the opposite of totalitarianism. For those of us who emerged from the grip of Communism, membership of the European Union is one of the main guarantees that we will never again revert to totalitarianism… It is something to be valued and never taken lightly. A collective conscience and memory of the past is a way of reinforcing the value of the present. (European Parliament 2009b)

The empirical part of this paper dissects specific claims on “European memory” which range from seeking equal legal treatment of communist and Nazi crimes, to calls for the overall condemnation of communism as a strand of political thought. These claims can be regarded as communication tools for venting resentment about the alleged imbalance of representation and power between the “new” and “old” members of the European Union—the traditional and emergent actors in European politics. Regardless of proponents' universalist framing of this struggle, diverse East European actors' claim to a place in a shared European memoryscape of twentieth-century totalitarianisms has often been understood as a particularistic project, deliberately challenging the hegemonic mnemonic narrative currently informing the contemporary European identity, broadly conceived. A genealogical inquiry into pan-European struggles to bring about a political, moral, and legal condemnation of the totalitarian communist legacy enables us to probe the diverse ways discourses constitute the subject positions of different East European actors in pan-European mnemopolitics, and to problematize the production of these discourses as a form of normative power.

It is through “memory,” after all, that a political community validates and reproduces, but also challenges itself (Levy and Sznaider 2010:4). “Memory” refers here to the officially endorsed, or politically coordinated and sanctioned remembrance of the past, manufactured by elites and shaped by institutional control. The “common memory” in question is really more a pan-European self-representational strategy, a form of discursive power rather than a cognitively shared collective remembrance. I approach the “European memory” as a particular discourse which is based on social and political negotiation and bargaining; it requires considerable social work and is therefore also reflective of the power relationships that constitute it (Pakier and Stråth 2010:6–7). As a genealogical approach is more concerned with an interpretation of what kind of politics is promoted by a moral system, rather than seeking to account for the conscious intentions of actors engaged in the process, it does not presume a necessary convergence between discursive and material, or structural, power (Price 1995:88).

While “memory” is the term generally used in the discourses under review, the notion of remembrance is preferred here for its emphasis on processuality instead of a fixed storage space. “Remembrance” is particularly apposite for this study due to its emphasis on the active process of remembering, as reflected in the sought institutionalization of the guidelines outlining the suggested public relationship to Europe's multiple totalitarian pasts. Likewise, the recognition pursued in transnationalizing the predominantly East European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes can only be understood as a dynamic process, rather than a static notion, for “even if obtained and institutionalized politically, [recognition] is always subject to new contestation” (Cooke 2009:29). Pan-European political declarations, legal initiatives, and international court decisions are thus taken as an exemplary embodiment or attempted reification of certain remembrance practices, as the putative “common European memory” in flesh.

The next section locates the subject matter against the backdrop of the argument on mnemonical cosmopolitanization, as recently developed in political sociology. Consequently, the contention over determining the nature of the largely East European claims for recognition, in the context of the struggle for condemning totalitarian communist regimes, is addressed. The workings of the conceptual framework are then illustrated with a brief genealogical cut into pan-European fora that have contributed, to differing degrees, to the construction of the remembrance of the communist legacy through a condemnatory normative prism. The chosen examples, adumbrated here for the purposes of brevity, together constitute a part of the latest episode in the transnational mnemopolitics in Europe, enabling us to delineate an emerging discourse on “remembering communism” in contemporary Europe.

Constructing a Cosmopolitan Memory?
Cosmopolitanization of memory is often regarded as a coproduct of European integration (Spohn and Eder 2005; Beck, Levy, and Sznaider 2009; Levy and Sznaider 2010). This is only symptomatic against the backdrop of the academic study of the European Union that is full of references to its alleged sui generis nature. The expected emergence of a shared memoryscape of Europe, with a harmonization of moral and political attitudes and remembrance practices in dealing with different pasts, is a characteristic expression of an assumption about the European Union's role in fundamentally reshaping the traditionally national patterns of social remembrance.

In light of recent critical revisions of the concept of mnemonical cosmopolitanization (Levy, Heinlein, and Breuer 2011), there are two relevant observations to take on board for making sense of the politics of pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes. First, just as it is with the “memory imperative” of the Holocaust (Levy and Sznaider 2002:101), the consolidation attempts of the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes underscore the urgency of remembrance for the future of Europe. Likewise, an attempted Europeanization in relating to “communist crimes” is built on a cosmopolitan ethic, or the “acknowledgement of some notion of common humanity that translates ethically into an idea of shared or common moral duties toward others by virtue of this humanity” (Lu 2000:245). Second, a major argumentative thread in the respective calls seeks recognition of the history and memories of the “Other” (or the incorporation of the historical experiences of East European countries in the pan-European “lessons” of totalitarianism and war), resonating with so-called methodological cosmopolitanism, aimed at including the “otherness of the other” (Levy and Sznaider 2002:103). As a Polish Member of the European Parliament, Adam Bielan has captured both strands of the discourse: “We must remember that understanding the past of the whole of Europe, and not only its western part, is the key to building a common future” (European Parliament 2009c).

The “Holocaust template” has a strong resonance in pan-European debates over the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes. The way the Holocaust was turned into a cosmopolitan equivalent of “evil” in Western historical consciousness has provided inspiration for the criminalizers of other historical legacies in their pursuit of international recognition of particular past experiences (Luik 2008). That is why the “Holocaust analogy” has become a sword for some and a shield for others in the contention over the reconstruction of a new moral order regarding the universal condemnability of totalitarian communist regimes, along with Nazism. Those critics disapproving of the way this analogy has been appropriated in the emerging normative discourse on communist regimes have denounced the pertinent East European-led mnemopolitics as an attempt at the kind of interpretive reversal that Foucault (1984:85–86) described as “seizing the … rules, to replace those who had used them, to disguise themselves so as to pervert them, invert their meaning, and redirect them against those who had initially imposed them.”
The Politics of Recognition
The struggle for pan-European moral and political condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes and the equal legal treatment of communist and Nazi crimes, driven largely by East European actors, features as the politics of recognition. Charles Taylor (1992) has distinguished between two meanings of the politics of recognition, arguably in the form of a historical sequence: the politics of equal dignity and the politics of difference. While the first of these focuses on what should be shared by all human beings (human rights, for instance), the second, the politics of difference, is related to social movements seeking to protect and celebrate distinct identities instead. Accordingly, the politics of equal dignity seeks the establishment of an identical set of rights and immunities, while the politics of difference (even though underlying its demand is a principle of universal equality) has a more particularistic flavor, for “what we are asked to recognize… is precisely this distinctness that has been ignored, glossed over, assimilated to a dominant or majority identity” (Taylor 1992:38–39). Taylor's argument's setup is essentially the nation versus the universal, whereas the transnational but not universal drops out.

While a concern for recognition of the communist legacy as part of the European remembrance of totalitarianism is not universally shared within Europe, it cannot quite be captured within the framework of the politics of equal dignity. Yet, for all its appeals to universal values, and emphasis on the right of the victims of totalitarian communist regimes to equal dignity and respect (see Bruzga 2008), it hardly fits Taylor's category of the politics of difference either. Following Maeve Cooke's (2009:79–80) emphatic deconstruction of Taylor's binary, it is fair to claim that the largely East European actor-driven transnational mnemopolitics of condemning totalitarian communist regimes entails both elements of the politics of equal dignity and a demand for the recognition of the substantive value of East European encounters with communism for the normative foundations of the European community. Thus, it is not the issue of seeking recognition of the East European difference (or identity politics) that is at stake here. Rather, while demanding pan-European recognition for the universally condemnable qualities and capacities of totalitarian communist regimes, this struggle also calls for recognition of the value of the distinctly East European experience that has not been universally shared in Europe. As such, the logic of the East European politics of recognition is similar to the functioning principle of mnemonic cosmopolitanism: it is not either universalism or particularism, but both a push for universal condemnation of the communist legacy and a call for simultaneous recognition of the specifically East European contribution to the European remembrance of totalitarianism.

As the empirical discussion demonstrates, condemnation of the crimes of communist regimes is generally sought in an abstract manner, or as formal recognition (Cooke 2009:81), and less frequently for the value of a substantive end (or concrete good). Seeking the establishment of the right to be a recognized part of a pan-European “memory” by legal provisions via the official institutional condemnation of communist regimes, and the criminalization of the denial of their crimes, thus runs parallel to a campaign for simply winning more prominent public acknowledgment of the crimes of totalitarian communist regimes (reflected inter alia in pan-European commemoration and memorialization policies; see Closa 2010a:13). Hence, the struggle to include the legacy of totalitarian communist regimes under the denouncing gaze of pan-European institutions of various kinds breaks down the binary suggested by Taylor (1992) according to which the politics of equal dignity corresponds to a type of social movement in which a concern for legal issues is paramount, while the politics of difference is related to social movements in which the principal issues are identity related (Cooke 2009:77). Moreover, as the spheres of recognition-seeking, criminal justice, and identity-building tend to overlap (Closa 2011:18), it might be difficult to distinguish in practice the nature of desired goods in the process of recognition-seeking. As Carlos Closa, who directed the European Commission-solicited Study on How the Memory of Crimes Committed by Totalitarian Regimes in Europe Is Dealt with in the Member States (2010b), uses the example of the former communist states to suggest that efforts to criminalize the denial of crimes committed by totalitarian communist regimes are primarily seeking recognition for sanctioning a certain kind of behavior as a crime, rather than striving for specific punishments or actual criminal proceedings (Closa 2011:20). “Criminalizing communism” is therefore more about seeking recognition of East European actors' equal standing in the European community—their right to be a recognized part of “European memory”—and less about the practical potency of the criminalizing measure as such.

The following empirical illustrations highlight that this is nonetheless a moot point for those actors seeking condemnation of the communist legacy in Europe and those perceiving this struggle as an anti-Russian movement in moral disguise. The former strive to unite Europe through an appeal to universal judgment on the communist experience of Eastern Europe and the need for equal dignity for the victims of different totalitarian regimes. Their claim to a “right to memory” (that is occasionally accompanied by a demand to hold equal rights under the law, or equal respect for equal suffering) indicates the degree to which the institutionalized European recognition is constitutive of their subjectivity as Europeans. The latter emphasize the particularity of the respective interpretation instead, understanding the condemnation campaign as a modern right-wing political revenge strike on the left, as well as a vicious, if emancipatory, blow by Russia's former East European dependents on their despised ex-colonial “master.” The proponents of the pan-European condemnation of communist regimes claim to seek recognition, in the first instance, as an abstract universal right. Meanwhile, their critics suspect concrete legal and political consequences, mainly to the detriment of contemporary Russia.

The pan-Europeanization of the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes has been further criticized as an attempt to sway the focal position of the Holocaust in the European memoryscape, to debate its significance as a constitutive event. This thread of criticism sees the venture as a deliberate ploy to relativize the criminalizers' own participation in the Holocaust, camouflaged behind their employment of the language of universal human rights and values of human dignity. That is the case in spite of the official discourse of the criminalizers of totalitarian communist regimes taking exquisite care with wording, emphasizing the uniqueness (and hence the particularity) of the Holocaust.

The two conceptual lines outlined above bear on the following empirical examples in distinct ways. A critical cosmopolitan perspective is helpful for illuminating the mnemonical transformations in contemporary Europe as it provides a diagnostic capacity for analyzing the interplay between the agendas of particularistic origin and universalistic drive in the transnational mnemopolitics over the remembrance of multiple totalitarian legacies in Europe. Understanding this pursuit as a struggle for recognition sheds further light on the predominantly East European rationale in this politics. As both parts of the suggested conceptual framework are informed by the interaction between a cosmopolitan ethic and processes of particularization, they are mutually reinforcing.
Europeanizing the Remembrance of the Communist Legacy in Europe
The following empirical section identifies and delineates the dynamics of the contending discourses on the communist legacy, pinpointing the features of totalitarian communist regimes that have come to be regarded as essential in disputes over (i) the definition of their legitimate remembrance; (ii) their labeling and evaluation, and (iii) (legal) standards of judgment to be applied across the main pan-European political and legal fora (cf. Price 1995: 89).

Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe
The Council of Europe has been a pioneering organization among those pan-European fora in which the search for political condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes has borne fruit. To date, the PACE has produced two important resolutions on the matter. The first of these is of a general character, dating back to 1996 (Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 1996). The second, and arguably the most comprehensive resolution on the matter to date (Žalimas 2010), was issued on January 25, 2006, whereby the Council of Europe strongly condemned crimes of totalitarian communist regimes, implicitly recognizing genocidal intent behind the communist liquidation policies of certain groups of people (Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006a; see also Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006b, c, 2010). The Assembly furthermore called on all communist or postcommunist parties in its member states to “clearly distance themselves from the crimes committed by totalitarian communist regimes and condemn them without any ambiguity” (Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006a:para.13).

While the full draft recommendation for a 2006 PACE resolution by the Swedish rapporteur Göran Lindblad was issued with a large majority by the Political Affairs Committee, it nonetheless did not receive the necessary two-thirds majority in the Parliamentary Assembly since the group of communist parties, including prominent Russian representatives, vehemently opposed the resolution. This turned out to be the main contingency in framing the undertaking rather cautiously as the “need for” international condemnation of crimes of totalitarian communist regimes, instead of calling a spade a spade; it also contributed to the obstruction of the draft recommendation calling on European governments to adopt a similar stance. The draft recommendation had indeed foreseen more thoroughgoing measures than the resolution adopted by the Assembly eventually contained, ranging from carrying out legal investigations into individuals engaged in “communist crimes” to the creation of commemoration and memorialization policies.

The debates accompanying the adoption of the Resolution 1481/2006 nonetheless reveal a straightforward call for the Europeanization of the treatment of the communist legacy. This is particularly the case when Europeanization is understood as Beck et al. (2009:120) define it: “to struggle for institutional answers to the barbarity of European modernity.” For them, the construction of a “cosmopolitan Europe” thus means “the institutional self-critique of the European way.” A typical trinity of arguments is presented in support of condemning totalitarian communist regimes: the need to raise general public awareness of the criminal legacy of communist regimes (see Mihkelson in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006b; and Herkel and Němcová in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c); the desire to morally restitute the victims (for the legal and economic restitution remains, due to the distance in time, in most cases unachievable anyway); and to politically condemn the ideology and methods of totalitarian communism in order to avoid the possible re-emergence of this model of governance in the future (Saks in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006b; Němcová in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c).

Representatives from the Baltic states, Bulgaria, Ukraine, and the Czech Republic further emphasized the symmetry between Nazi and communist crimes and pointed to the vital connection between the willingness to approach one's own history critically and the potential for true democratization, clearly alluding to the prospects for democracy in Russia. Opinions diverged on whether or not the communist ideology should be deemed guilty as such: while there were voices among the pro-condemnation group arguing relentlessly that communism could “never be reformed and is absolutely incompatible with the notion of democracy” (Němcová in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c), others preferred to leave this thorny issue for intellectual discussion and out of the debate over the PACE report.

What was generally presented as at stake by those representatives calling for the condemnation of the crimes of totalitarian communist regimes in the debates leading to the adoption of the respective resolution was not criminal justice for the perpetrators, or reparatory justice to materially repair and compensate for prior wrongs, but rather historical justice—the creation of historical accountings of communism in order to redefine the European experience of totalitarianism more comprehensively, and to reconstruct a common European identity accordingly. The arguments presented in support of the international condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes spoke very much for the connection between a particular relationship to the communist legacy and modern European sensibilities. They highlighted a request for the formal acknowledgment of equal dignity for the victims of totalitarian communist regimes rather than seeking recognition for the value of a substantive end.

As with any disciplining discourse, the attempted condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes drew considerable resistance from numerous national and ideological quarters. Greek, Cypriot, Czech, and Russian representatives, some of them with explicitly communist party affiliation, reached for a standard defense in support of the communist cause in the PACE debate of January 25, 2006. This defense centered on the Soviet Union's role in the fight against Nazism and the allegedly consequent impossibility of equating the legacies of the Soviet and Nazi regimes. Not only was it claimed to be “unacceptable to equate the word ‘communist’ with crime” given the impossibility of “criminaliz[ing] class struggle” (Kanelli in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006b), but “the sacrifice of the lives of twenty millions Russians” could never be forgotten either (Christodoulides in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c). Critics read Lindblad's draft resolution as a text aimed at “stigmatization of the communist ideology as such,” and therefore, a “merely political declaration and a dangerous and unworthy attempt for rewriting of history” (Konečná in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c). The push for international condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes was accordingly labeled “a reactionary and ideological campaign” (Konečná, ibid.); “a desperate attempt by conservative and extremist forces to defocus the people of Europe from their day-to-day problems” (Christodoulides in Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006c). A Russian communist representative, Gennady Zyuganov, even reproached the condemnation campaign as a push to “revert back to fascism” (Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly 2006b). Depicting the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes in exclusive either/or terms vis-à-vis the condemnation of Nazism, the critics denounced the universalistic appeal of the campaign.

While the adopted resolution was ultimately quite restrained in light of the demands of the vehement anti-communists, as well as legally non-binding, the European Court of Human Rights, established under the auspices of the Council of Europe, has managed to address calls for criminal justice for the victims of communist crimes in a more sustained and comprehensive manner. From the standpoint of international law, a political resolution, such as PACE's 1481/2006, could be considered as merely a subsidiary tool or additional source to interpret relevant rules of international law regarding the qualification of the international crimes committed by communist regimes as crimes against humanity, war crimes, or genocide (Žalimas 2010:8). ECtHR rulings, however, are binding to those states who are contracting parties to the European Convention on Human Rights. They have thus given a more concrete substance to criminalizing communism, functioning as a symbol of recognition-seeking for the value of distinctive experiences with communism for the normative reformation of the European community.
European Court of Human Rights
The legal basis for international condemnation of the crimes of communist regimes can be found in the customary international law principles recognized in the Statute of the Nuremberg International Military Tribunal, and the jurisprudence of this Tribunal.

The debate over holding the standard formulated at Nuremberg to be universal in the context of WWII acquired wider resonance for the overall pan-European assessment of the totalitarian communist legacy, with the consecutive rulings of the ECtHR in the case of Kononov v. Latvia. Former Soviet partisan, Vasily Kononov, had been convicted by the Latvian courts for leading a group of Soviet partisans who killed nine inhabitants of the Eastern Latvian village of Mazie Bati on May 27, 1944, for their alleged collaboration with the Germans occupying the country at the time. The 2008 judgment by the ECtHR's former Third Section found Latvia to be in violation of Article 7 of the European Convention on Human Rights which enshrines the prohibition of retroactive application of criminal law when convicting Kononov for a war crime. As Judge Egbert Myjer of the Netherlands put it, in the concurring opinion to the chamber's judgment (Myjer 2008:65): “… the Nazis and their collaborators were entirely in the wrong and those who fought against the Nazis … were completely in the right.” Just two years later, however, the Grand Chamber of the ECtHR reversed the previous judgment of the Court's Third Section (European Court of Human Rights 2010). Symptomatic of the dividing lines of the debate, the Russian Federation intervened in the process before the Grand Chamber as a third-party state in support of Kononov, while Lithuania stepped in for Latvia.

Contra the openly discriminatory understanding of war crimes that had informed the original ECtHR ruling in the Kononov case, the Grand Chamber upheld the war crimes conviction of Kononov by the previous rulings of the Latvian courts. Thereby, the Court established an important precedent in applying the Nuremberg standards to the winners of WWII, approving the measuring of all international crimes committed in the context of the war by the universal normative benchmark, regardless of their perpetrators' allegiance to the supposedly more rightful jus ad bellum (Mälksoo 2011). The successful Latvian appeal thus constituted a major victory for the broader politics of seeking recognition for the distinct East European experiences with twentieth-century totalitarian regimes, and the legal treatment of communist crimes on par with the crimes of the Nazis. Sandra Kalniete, Latvian chair of the European Parliament's informal group, Reconciliation of European Histories, welcomed the Grand Chamber's judgment as a step toward historical justice. In turn, the Russian Ministry of Foreign Affairs (2010) called the Court's final judgment “a very dangerous precedent” that represented:
an attempt to cast doubt on several key legal and political principles that emerged following the Second World War and the postwar settlement in Europe, particularly with regard to the prosecution of the Nazi war criminals … [T]he Grand Chamber has actually agreed today with those who seek to revise the outcome of World War II and whitewash the Nazis and their accomplices … [T]he decision seriously damages the credibility of the Council of Europe in general and may be viewed as an attempt to draw new dividing lines in Europe and to destroy the continent's emerging consensus on pan-European standards and values.

The debates about, and repercussions of, the Kononov case in the ECtHR provide an emblematic illustration of the fundamental divide between the universalistic and particularistic assessments of communist crimes, emphasizing ongoing contestations over the hegemonic mnemonic narrative of twentieth-century totalitarianisms and war in Europe at large. This case vividly exemplifies the multiple “fronts” of the East European struggle for seeking political and legal recognition of communist crimes. Moreover, the discussions surrounding the Kononov case confirm the observation about how justice established in trials addressing human rights abuses can itself become a new form of remembrance and, consequently, the inaugurated law a medium of collective memory (Levy and Sznaider 2010:18–19). As Levy and Sznaider remind us (2007:166), it was “ultimately … the memory of the Second World War and not the Holocaust that stood at the center of both the Nuremberg trials and the nascent idea of a European community.” The final ruling of the ECtHR in the Kononov case could accordingly be read as a codification of an emerging remembrance at the European level, as it encapsulates the intertwining of the remembrance of WWII with a broader assessment of the communist legacy for Europe. In this sense, “the jurisprudence serves a fixative role,” as the finality of legal judgment can eventually help to settle contested histories (Buyse and Hamilton 2011:6). Judgments, such as the ECtHR Grand Chamber's ruling in the Kononov v. Latvia case, are thus transformative opportunities for the wider European assessment of the crimes committed by communist regimes.
Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe
Yet another such transformative opportunity was provided by the OSCE Parliamentary Assembly's (PA) adoption of the Resolution “On Divided Europe Reunited: Promoting Human Rights and Civil Liberties in the OSCE Region in the 21st Century,” in 2009, at the annual session of the Assembly in Vilnius. This resolution, also known as the Vilnius Declaration, compared the two major totalitarian regimes in twentieth-century Europe, “the Nazi and the Stalinist, which brought about genocide, violations of human rights and freedoms, war crimes and crimes against humanity” (2009:48, para.3). While acknowledging the uniqueness of the Holocaust, the resolution reminded the OSCE participating states of their commitment “to clearly and unequivocally condemn totalitarianism” (ibid. para. 5). The Declaration further supported the initiative of the European Parliament to proclaim August 23, the day the Molotov-Ribbentrop Pact was signed, in 1939, as “a Europe-wide Day of Remembrance for Victims of Stalinism and Nazism,” (ibid. para. 10) and urged its member states to increase awareness of totalitarian crimes. The Vilnius Declaration encouraged all OSCE members to take a “united stand against all totalitarian rule from whatever ideological background” (ibid. para. 11) and criticized the “glorification of totalitarian regimes, including the holding of public demonstrations glorifying the Nazi or Stalinist past” (ibid. para. 17).

Critics from the Russian Duma and elsewhere interpreted the Vilnius Declaration as an assault on established historical memory (cf. Kurilla 2009:5), as yet another adventure of the “east European far right” (Katz 2010a), constituting “the new code for double genocide, Holocaust obfuscation and the special brand of east European antisemitism” (Katz 2010b). As a Guardian columnist evocatively concluded, “The pretense that Soviet repression reached anything like the scale or depths of Nazi savagery… is a mendacity that tips toward Holocaust denial” (Milne 2009). As is characteristic in the operation of moral discourse on communist regimes, the Vilnius Declaration epitomizes the contestation for mnemonic hegemony in Europe, featuring further the resistance from various quarters to the attempted reconfiguration of the pertinent pan-European narrative. While critics typically depict the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes as a zero-sum problem vis-à-vis Nazi crimes, proponents emphasize the recognition of this particular legacy for the integrity of the normative foundations of Europe, and a prerequisite for its future thereof.
The European Union
Most prominently, the Eastern enlargement of the European Union provided an enabling condition for the institutionalization of a moral assessment of the communist legacy. Since the 2005 European Parliament (EP) resolution, The Future of Europe Sixty Years after the Second World War, the European Union has become an evocative arena for making parallel claims about recognition of the substantive value of the largely East European encounters with communism for the historical consciousness and “conscience” of the European community, along with calls for a more abstract normative condemnation of totalitarian regimes of different stripes.

The key milestones in this process include the European Parliament's 2008 and 2009 hearings on crimes committed by totalitarian communist regimes, the proclamation of August 23 as European Day of Remembrance for Victims of Stalinism and Nazism in 2008, and a subsequent EP resolution calling for the implementation of this day of commemoration (2009a). The adjacent debates have been replete with calls to close the gap between the victims of Nazism and communism and to remove the double standards applied to Nazi and communist regimes. Indicative of the East European mnemonical recognition-seeking in this venture, the resolution on European conscience and totalitarianism (2009a) was tabled by mostly East European (Baltic, Polish, Czech, Hungarian, and Romanian) representatives (the cosponsors also included Belgian, German, and Swedish politicians). This resolution succeeded an earlier Prague Declaration on European Conscience and Communism, adopted on June 3, 2008, after an eponymic international conference at the Czech Senate. The Prague Declaration, in turn, resonated with the prior debates at PACE, emphasizing the quintessential themes of Europeanizing the remembrance of the criminality of communist regimes by underscoring the importance of the (right) remembering of the past for shaping the (right) future; the impossibility of European unification without the “reunification” of its history; and repeating the common accusation about the unbalanced books of communism and Nazism. In unprecedentedly strong and assertive language, the signatories, which included Václav Havel, Joachim Gauck, Göran Lindblad, and Vytautas Landsbergis, among others, called for the “recognition of communism as an integral and horrific part of Europe's common history,” as well as “European and international pressure for effective condemnation of the past communist crimes and for efficient fight against ongoing communist crimes” (Prague Declaration on European Conscience and Communism 2008:para. 6).

The EU-wide campaign for the condemnation of the totalitarian communist legacy is likewise underpinned by the assumption that Europe cannot be united as long as West and East do not agree on a common understanding of the shared history of communism and Nazism (Pleštinská; Romagnoli in the European Parliament 2009c). Allegedly, it is the mental and spiritual enlargement of the European Union that is at stake here, “the enlargement of European awareness of the massive crimes against humanity,” and “the integration of European historic perception… of prejudices and different views of history” (Kelam in European Parliament 2009b; cf. Figel calling for “an expansion of awareness, an expansion of memory and an expansion of respect and responsibility” ibid.).

Demands for concrete legal implications in the struggle for pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes are increasingly expressed through looser transnational formats, particularly after the unsuccessful East European appeal on broadening the coverage of the European Council (2008) on combating racism and xenophobia. The Declaration on Crimes of Communism (2010), the signatories to which range from politicians to former political prisoners and current human rights advocates, is an emblematic illustration of this trend. The Platform of European Memory and Conscience, established in Prague in 2011 in order to provide an umbrella institution for organizations dealing with research, documentation, awareness raising, and education about totalitarian regimes in twentieth-century Europe, is yet another. Reflecting its predominantly East European origins, the Platform currently embraces relevant institutions from Bulgaria, Canada, the Czech Republic, Estonia, Germany, Hungary, Iceland, Latvia, Lithuania, Moldova, Netherlands, Poland, Romania, Slovakia, Slovenia, Sweden, Ukraine, and the United States. The creation of a supranational judicial body for the legal settlement of communist crimes remains high on the Platform's political agenda, punctuating the shifting accent of the campaign from historical to criminal justice, or from a general condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes to a more concretely defined recognition-seeking with tangible legal implications.

The Declaration on Crimes of Communism (2010) accordingly called for the establishment of a new international court, with a seat within the European Union, for the condemnation of crimes of communism “in a similar way as the Nazi crimes [and] the crimes committed in former Yugoslavia… were condemned and sentenced,” (para. 4) for leaving the crimes of communism unpunished would mean “disregard of and thus weakening of international law” (para. 5). While the declaration emphasized that communism needs to be condemned in a similar way to Nazism, the signatories pointed out that they were nonetheless “not equating the respective crimes of Nazism and communism” which “should each be studied and judged on their own terrible merits” (para. 7). They did highlight explicitly, however, that “[c]ommunist ideology and communist rule contradict the European Convention of Human Rights and the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the EU” (ibid.). Calling upon the European Commission and European Council of Justice and Home Affairs to adopt a Framework Decision introducing a pan-European ban on excusing, denying, or trivializing the crimes of communism, the underlying message of the Declaration highlighted how the fulfillment of this ambition would crown the transnational endeavor to equalize the juridified remembrance of the two main totalitarian legacies in Europe.
Conclusion
A genealogical approach contains some useful pointers toward an international political sociology of the emerging European remembrance of totalitarian communism. The transnational in this struggle remains to be adequately populated in future research. An inquiry into the sources and meanings of the nascent pan-European remembrance of totalitarian communist regimes has underscored recognition-seeking, the struggle for mnemonical hegemony, contingency, and resistance in the operation of this moral discourse.

The argument I have made here is that the shifting dynamics in contestation of the normative condemnation of the communist legacy in Europe—from earlier PACE debates to recent efforts to extend the European Union's legal coverage to criminalize the denial of totalitarian communist crimes—are indicative of the changing edifice of the European response to its twentieth-century encounters with totalitarianism. The discursive linkage of communist regimes with criminality has enabled the reinforcement of their moral illegitimacy and incompatibility with “European values.” While the flow of political declarations by various European organizations supporting the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes has been quite noteworthy, the legal score card of institutionalizing the denouncement of communist regimes has nonetheless remained rather checkered. The attempted Europeanization of the condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes has remained politically contentious. Yet, the gradual consolidation of a broadly anti-totalitarian stance as an important part of “European memory” of the twentieth century has left the Russian Federation among the few active resisters of this frame.

As moral universalism, postnationalist aspirations, and a legalizing drive continue to inform the largely East European-led efforts toward a pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes, the conceptual mold of mnemonical cosmopolitanization remains useful for understanding the process of subjecting national memories of communism to a common remembrance patterning (see Levy and Sznaider 2007:160). The emerging discourse owes much to the concerted efforts of various East European actors to increase public awareness and endorse condemnation of the crimes of communist regimes.

The ongoing argument over the place that the communist legacy should occupy in Europeans' collective sense of themselves is reflective of the wider politics of recognition for making East European experiences part of a shared mnemonic inventory of the enlarged European community. The European Union, in particular, has become “a recognition order” of sorts (Closa 2010a:17). The transnational mnemopolitics of condemning communist regimes in Europe illustrates the mutual constitution of particular attachments and cosmopolitan orientations (cf. Levy et al. 2011:140). As such, it constitutes a good site for a genealogical reflection, highlighting the jolted emergence of a pan-European remembrance of communist regimes as indictment.
Footnotes
This research was funded by the European Union through the European Social Fund's Mobilitas post-doctoral fellowship, and HERA Memory at War project. I am grateful to the MAW project members at Cambridge, Alex Astrov, Tarak Barkawi, Duncan Bell, Jenny Edkins, Toomas Hiio, Lauri Mälksoo, Lutz Niethammer, Eva-Clarita Pettai, and the three anonymous reviewers for comments on draft versions of this article.
European Union
HERA
Lithuania, Latvia, Bulgaria, Hungary, Romania, and the Czech Republic.
Many critics regard the epithet “totalitarian” as a hypocritical, if necessary, nod toward soothing the Euro-communists, since Europe is allegedly yet to know a non-totalitarian communist regime. This is well reflected in the debates analyzed in this article, which frequently argue for the ontological criminality of communism as a house of political thought, rather than seeking to determine the degree of repressiveness contingent to actual communist regimes.
While the calls to acknowledge and condemn the criminal legacy of communism occasionally embrace a global audience (aiming at China in particular), these initiatives are beyond the scope of this paper.
The interpretations of the paper draw on Foucaultian discourse analysis which takes discourses not only to contain linguistic expressions, but also to generate modes of power and exclusion, thus emphasizing the relationship between the formation of discursive practices and wider processes of social and cultural change.
The intertwining of remembrances of WWII and the communist legacy is characteristically manifested in discourses criticizing the pan-European condemnation of totalitarian communist regimes as the undertaking of “the losers of the Second World War” (Guerreiro in European Parliament debate 2009c).
See eureconciliation.wordpress.com/about/. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
As reflected in the exchanges of fervently anti- and pro-communist arguments in PACE by the representatives of a single ex-communist country (the Czech Republic's Němcová and Konečná). Another example is provided by the activities of Dovid, Katz, a Yiddish scholar based in Lithuania, against the purported “Holocaust obfuscation” accompanying the movement seeking pan-European condemnation of communist crimes.
Against this backdrop, it is noteworthy that The International Holocaust Remembrance Alliance (formerly the Task Force for International Cooperation on Holocaust Education, Remembrance, and Research) has recently established a specialized committee to address “comparative genocide.”
Critics have pointed to the alleged abuse of this lever by the European People's Party (EPP) against its left-wing political opponents in the European Parliament.
The result—as the founding document of the Platform of European Memory and Conscience evocatively shows—is a curious mix of both claims. While the underlying rationale for the Platform is indeed the comparability and equivalence of Nazi and communist crimes, a nod to the core narrative informing the hierarchical remembrance of twentieth-century totalitarianisms is nonetheless made at the very beginning of the establishing agreement by taking dutiful notice of “the exceptionality and uniqueness of Holocaust.” See http://www.memoryandconscience.eu/wp-content/uploads/2011/12/Agreement-and-Statute-of-the-Platform1.pdf. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
Today, Göran Lindblad is the President of the Platform of European Memory and Conscience.
See http://eureconciliation.wordpress.com/2010/05/18/a-pivotal-judgment-of-the-echr-no-impunity-for-perpetrators-of-war-crimes-sandra-kalniete-mep/. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
© 2014 International Studies Association
References
Bartelson Jens. (1995) A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Beck Ulrich, Levy Daniel, Sznaider Natan. (2009) Cosmopolitanization of Memory: The Politics of Forgiveness and Restitution. In Cosmopolitanism in Practice, edited by Nowicka Magdalena, Rovisco Maria. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Berger Thomas U.. (2012) War, Guilt, and World Politics after World War II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bruzga Andrius. (2008) Lithuania Has Earned Its Place in Europe. Letter by the Lithuanian Ambassador to the United States to The Jewish Daily Forward, July 11. Available at http://forward.com/articles/13695/July—/. (Accessed September 6, 2013.)
Buyse Antoine, Hamilton Michael. (2011) Introduction. In Transitional Jurisprudence and the ECHR: Justice, Politics, and Rights, edited by Buyse Antoine, Hamilton Michael. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Challand Benoît. (2009) 1989, Contested Memories and the Shifting Cognitive Maps of Europe. European Journal of Social Theory 12 (3): 397–408.Abstract/FREE Full Text
Closa Carlos. (2010a) Negotiating the Past: Claims for Recognition and Policies of Memory in the EU. Working Paper 08/2010. Madrid: Instituto de Políticas y Bienes Públicos (IPP).
Closa Carlos. (2010b) Study on How the Memory of Crimes Committed by Totalitarian Regimes in Europe is Dealt With in the Member States. Madrid: Institute for Public Goods and Policy.
Closa Carlos. (2011) Dealing with the Past: Memory and European Integration. Jean Monnet Working Paper 01/11. New York: NYU School of Law.
Cooke Maeve. (2009) Beyond Dignity and Difference: Revisiting the Politics of Recognition. European Journal of Social Theory 8 (1): 76–95.
Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. (1996) Resolution 1096 on Measures to Dismantle the Heritage of Former Communist Totalitarian Systems. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly.
Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. (2006a) Need for International Condemnation of Crimes of Totalitarian Communist Regimes. Resolution 1481/2006. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly.
Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. (2006b) Report of the Fifth Sitting of 2006 Ordinary Session. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. Available at http://assembly.coe.int/Main.asp?link=/Documents/Records/2006/E/0601251500E.htm#4. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. (2006c) Report of the Fifth Sitting of 2006 Ordinary Session (First Part, Addendum 1). Available at http://www.assembly.coe.int/Main.asp?link=/Documents/Records/2006/E/0601251500EAD1.htm. (Accessed September 7, 2013.)
Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly. (2010) Resolution 1723 on Commemorating the Victims of the Great Famine (Holodomor) in the Former USSR. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Parliamentary Assembly.
Courtois Stéphane, Werth Nicolas, Panné Jean-Louis, Paczkowski Andrzej, Bartosek Karel, Margolin Jean-Louis. (1999) The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Declaration on Crimes of Communism. (2010) Prague. Available at http://www.crimesofcommunism.eu/declaration.html. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
Elbe Stefan. (2001) ‘We good Europeans…’: Genealogical Reflections on the Idea of Europe. Millennium: Journal of International Studies 30 (2): 259–283.CrossRef
European Commission. (2010) The Memory of the Crimes Committed by Totalitarian Regimes in Europe. Report from the Commission to the European Parliament and to the Council, Brussels, COM(2010) 783.
European Council. (2008) Framework Decision 2008/913/JHA on Combating Certain Forms and Expressions of Racism and Xenophobia by Means of Criminal Law. Brussels: European Council.
European Court of Human Rights. (2010) Grand Chamber Judgment on the Case of Kononov v. Latvia. Strasbourg: European Court of Human Rights.
European Parliament. (2005) The Future of Europe Sixty Years after the Second World War. Resolution on the Sixtieth Anniversary of the End of the Second World War in Europe on 8 May 1945. Brussels: European Parliament.
European Parliament. (2009a) European Conscience and Totalitarianism. Resolution P6_TA(2009)0213. Brussels: European Parliament.
European Parliament. (2009b) European Conscience and Totalitarianism (Debate), March 25. Strasbourg: European Parliament. Available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu/sides/getDoc.do?pubRef=-//EP//TEXT+CRE+20090325+ITEM-010+DOC+XML+V0//EN. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
European Parliament. (2009c) European Conscience and Totalitarianism (debate), April 2. Brussels: European Parliament. Available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu/sides/getDoc.do?type=CRE&reference=20090402&secondRef=ITEM-010&language=EN&ring=P6-RC-2009-0165#4-176. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
Foucault Michel. (1984) Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In The Foucault Reader, edited by Rabinow Paul. New York: Pantheon Books.
Jarausch Konrad H.. (2010) Nightmares or Daydreams? A Postscript on the Europeanisation of Memories. In A European Memory? Contested Histories and Politics of Remembrance, edited by Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. New York: Berghahn Books.
Judt Tony. (2010) Postwar: A History of Europe since 1945. London: Vintage Books.
Judt Tony, Snyder Timothy. (2012) Thinking the Twentieth Century: Intellectuals and Politics in the Twentieth Century. New York: Penguin Press.
Karlsson Klas-Göran. (2010) The Uses of History and the Third Wave of Europeanisation. In A European Memory? Contested Histories and Politics of Remembrance, edited by Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. New York: Berghahn Books.
Katz Dovid. (2009) On Three Definitions: Genocide; Holocaust Denial; Holocaust Obfuscation. In A Litmus Test Case of Modernity: Examining Modern Sensibilities and the Public Domain in the Baltic States at the Turn of the Century, edited by Donskis Leonidas. Bern: Peter Lang.
Katz Dovid. (2010a) Halting Holocaust Obfuscation. The Guardian, January 8. Available at http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2010/jan/08/holocaust-baltic-lithuania-latvia. (Accessed September 7, 2013.)
Katz Dovid. (2010b) Why is the US Silent on ‘Double Genocide’? The Guardian, December 21. Available at http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/cifamerica/2010/dec/21/double-genocide-baltic-us-europe. (Accessed September 7, 2013.)
Kurilla Ivan I.. (2009) Memory Wars in the Post-Soviet Space. PONARS Eurasia Policy Memo 63, September. Available at http://www.ponarseurasia.org/sites/default/files/policy-memos-pdf/pepm_063.pdf. (Accessed September 7, 2013.)
Leggewie Claus. (2010) Seven Circles of European Memory. Eurozine, December 20.
Levy Daniel, Sznaider Natan. (2002) Memory Unbound: The Holocaust and the Formation of Cosmopolitan Memory. European Journal of Social Theory 5 (1): 87–106.Abstract/FREE Full Text
Levy Daniel, Sznaider Natan. (2007) Memories of Europe. Cosmopolitanism and Its Others. In Cosmopolitanism and Europe, edited by Rumford Chris. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press.
Levy Daniel, Sznaider Natan. (2010) Human Rights and Memory: Essays on Human Rights. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Levy Daniel, Heinlein Michel, Breuer Lars. (2011) Reflexive Particularism and Cosmopolitanization: The Reconfiguration of the National. Global Networks 11 (2): 139–159.CrossRef
Littoz-Monnet Annabelle. (2012) The EU Politics of Remembrance: Can Europeans Remember Together? West European Politics 35 (5): 1182–1202.CrossRef
Lu Catherine. (2000) The One and Many Faces of Cosmopolitanism. The Journal of Political Philosophy 8 (2): 244–267.CrossRefWeb of Science
Luik Jüri. (2008) Our Duty. Diplomaatia (March): 16–18.
Mälksoo Maria. (2009) The Memory Politics of Becoming European: The East European Subalterns and the Collective Memory of Europe. European Journal of International Relations 15 (4): 653–680.Abstract/FREE Full Text
Mälksoo Lauri. (2011) Kononov v. Latvia. The American Journal of International Law 105 (1): 101–108.CrossRef
Milne Seumas. (2009) This Rewriting of History Is Spreading Europe's Poison. The Guardian, September 9. Available at http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2009/sep/09/second-world-war-soviet-pact. (Accessed September 7, 2013.)
Müller Jan-Werner. (2010) On ‘European Memory’: Some Conceptual and Normative Remarks. In A European Memory? Contested Histories and Politics of Remembrance, edited by Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. New York: Berghahn Books.
Myjer Judge. (2008) Concurring Opinion in the Kononov v. Latvia Judgment. Kononov v. Latvia, no. 36376/04. Strasbourg: European Court of Human Rights.
Nietzsche Friedrich. (1967) On the Genealogy of Morals. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House.
OSCE Parliamentary Assembly. (2009) On Divided Europe Reunited: Promoting Human Rights and Civil Liberties in the OSCE Region in the 21st Century. Final Vilnius Declaration. Vilnius: OSCE Parliamentary Assembly. Available at http://www.kommunisten.de/attachments/497_Resolution_OSZE_20090703.pdf. (Accessed January 28, 2014.)
Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. (2010) Introduction. A European Memory? In A European Memory? Contested Histories and Politics of Remembrance, edited by Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. New York: Berghahn Books.
Prague Declaration on European Conscience and Communism. (2008) Prague, June 3. Available at http://praguedeclaration.eu/. (Accessed August 5, 2013.)
Price Richard. (1995) A Genealogy of the Chemical Weapons Taboo. International Organization 49 (1): 73–103.CrossRefWeb of Science
Rostoks Toms. (2011) Debating 20th Century History in Europe: The European Parliament and the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe Compared. In The Geopolitics of History in Latvian-Russian Relations, edited by Muižnieks Nils. Riga: Academic Press of the University of Latvia.
Russian Ministry of Foreign Affairs. (2010) Statement by the Russian Foreign Ministry Following the Pronouncement on May 17, 2010, of the Ruling of the Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights in the Case of Vasily Kononov.
Spohn Willfried, Eder Klaus Eds. (2005) Collective Memory in the Enlarging Europe: The Effects of Integration and Enlargement. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.
Taylor Charles. (1992) The Politics of Recognition. In Multiculturalism and ‘The Politics of Recognition’. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Troebst Stefan. (2010) Halecki Revisited: Europe's Conflicting Cultures of Remembrance. In A European Memory? Contested Histories and Politics of Remembrance, edited by Pakier Małgorzata, Stråth Bo. New York: Berghahn Books.
Vucetic Srdjan. (2011) Genealogy as a Research Tool in International Relations. Review of International Studies 37 (3): 1295–1312.CrossRefWeb of Science
Žalimas Dainius. (2010) Crimes Committed by the Communist Regimes from the Standpoint of International Legislation: Lithuanian case study. Presentation at the Institute for the Study of Totalitarian Regimes Conference on the Crimes of Communist Regimes, Prague, February 24–26.

View Abstract


CODE: YY